The Asbury Theological Journal Volume 43 No. 1

Page 1


!"#$%&

!"##$%&'%()*+ !"#$%&#'()*%'&"

,"--"./%0'%&1223-4

SPRING

88

!"#$%&&#"'#$ '()&*#")+,-'./%#-#01',23'4%&-%1'5*63)%&

0'%5."6"-%78(922"$

!"#$%&&#"'#$ '7%*/#3)&*'(#-)2%&&'()&*#"1

!"#$%&#'()'"+#,%&-).'/!(

VOL. 43 • NO. 1

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



SPRING 1988 Volume 43, Number l

Editorial Note . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . David R . Bauer

4

Tribute to Robert A. Traina David L . McKenna

7

Intentions and the Logic of Interpretation ... . J l William J . Abraham Mediated Meaning: A Contextualist Approach to Hermeneutical Method . . . . . . . . 27 Jerry H. Gill Pirke' Abot 1:2(3) and the Synoptic Redactions of the Commands to Love God and Neighbor .... 43 Eugene E. Lemcio Some Observations On The New Testament Concept of "Witness" . .. . . . . . . . . 55 Donald G. Miller Jo hn 20:22, Once More .... .. . . . . . . . . . . . 73 Robert W. L yon Book Reviews .. . . .... . ...... .. . . . . . . . 87 Published in April and October by Asbury Theological Seminary Postmaster: Send address changes to The Asbury Theological Journal Asbury Theological Seminary 204 North Lexington Wilmore , KY 40390- 1199 USPS 547-440


!

!

1


SPRING 1988 Volume 43, Number 1 David L. McKenna Publisher Robert T. Bridges Editor in Chief Laurence W. Wood Editor

Eugene E. Carpenter Associate Editor J. Steven O'Malley Book Review Editor Eric H. Johnson Managing Editor

Carolyn B. Smith Assistant Editor Sylvia Duttweiler Editorial Assistant

EDITORIAL BOARD David L. McKenna President and Publisher Robert T. Bridges Vice President for Seminary Advancement, Editor in Chief Laurence W. Wood Professor of Philosophy of R eligion , Editor Eugene E. Carpenter Associate Professor of Old T estament, Associate Editor Eric H. Johnson Director of Communications, Managing Editor

J. Steven O'Malley Professor of Church Hi story and Historical Theology, Book Review Editor David D. Bundy Assistant Professor of Christian Origins Allan Coppedge Associate Professor of Theology Donald Demaray Granger E. and Anna A. Fisher Professor of Preaching

BOARD OF REFERENCE George W. Coats Professor of Old Testament. Lexington Theological Seminary Stanley Hauerwas Professor of Theological Ethics. Duke University

Helmut Nausner Superintendent Methodist Church in Austria W. Richard Stegner Professor of New Testament . Garrett-Evangelical Theological S eminary

Printed in U.SA.

!

!

2


! THE ASBURY THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL provides a scholarly forum for thorough discussion of issues relevant to Christian thought and faith, and to the nature and mission of the church. The Journal addresses those concerns and ideas across the curriculum which interface with Christian thought, life and ministry. The primary resource for contributions to The Journal is the Asbury Seminary faculty who engage in dialogue with both the roots of our religious heritage and contemporary thought. Scholars from other academic disciplines and various backgrounds are invited to submit articles for publication. The positions espoused in articles in The Journal do not necessarily represent the views of the editors or of Asbury Theological Seminary. Books for review and articles for consideration should be mailed to: Eric H. Johnson, Asbury Theological Seminary, Wilmore, KY 40390-1199. Telephone (606) 858-3581. Manuscripts should be in English and typed double-spaced on white bond paper, 8 x 11 inches, with an accompanying computer disk copy when that is possible. Sermons, poetry and devotional materials are not used. Unsolicited manuscripts will not be returned unless a self-addressed envelope with sufficient postage is provided. Queries are welcome, and a style sheet is available upon request. Modest honorarium payments to authors follow acceptance. Articles in The Journal are indexed in The Christian Periodical Index and Religion Index One: Periodicals (RIO); book reviews are indexed in Index to Book Reviews in Religion (!BRR ) . Both RIO and IBRR are published by the American Theological Library Association, 5600 South Woodlawn A venue, Chicago, IL 60637, and are available online through BRS Information Technologies and DIALOG Information Services. Articles, starting with vol. 43, are abstracted in Religious and Theological Abstracts. Volumes in microfilm of The Asbury Theological Journal (Vol. 41-) and The Asbury Seminarian (Vol. 1-40) are available from University Microfilms International, 300 North Zeeb Road, Ann Arbor, MI 48106. Articles and reviews may be copied for personal or internal use, and permission to reprint all or portions of any of the contents may be granted upon request to the managing editor. Subscriptions: One year (2 issues), $5.00 (outside the U.S. $8.00); Two years, $8.00 ($14.00); Three years, $11 .00 ($20.00).

3


!

Editorial Note This Asbury Theological Journal is dedicated to Professor Robert A. Traina on the occasion of his retirement from th e faculty of Asbury Theological Seminary. Professor Traina was born on August 27, 1921, in Chicago, the His father was a member of the son of Italian immigrants. Methodist Episcopal Church, but served as lay pastor to the Italian Mission Free Methodist Church in Melrose Park, Illinois. In this church Robert was nurtured in the Christian faith and first sensed the call to parish ministry at the age of 16. Professor Traina majored in religious studies and minored in Greek (classical and biblical) at Spring Arbor College and Seattle Pacific College . During these years his interest in biblical studies was kindled. While a student at Seattle Pacific, Professor Traina became aware of the program at The Biblical Seminary in New York; and in the fall of 1943 he and his new bride, Jane Odell, arrived in New York where he began his seminary education. The Biblical Seminary in New York, founded in 1900 by the Yale-educated Se mitist Wilbert Webster White, had gained a worldwide reputation for the "inductive method" of the stud y of the English Bible. Courses in English Bible formed the center of the curriculum; the emphasis was upon the direct study of the Bible, and the goal was to allow the text to speak on its own terms, challenging all presuppositions and conforming the whole person to its message. Professor Traina found this approach to be a liberating experience. He had come to seminary, according to his own account, with a deductive personality, and the inductive approach changed his orientation to life and to the Bible. The Biblical Seminary emphasized effective and creative teaching, and professor Traina encountered there masters of the classroom, including Caroline Palmer, Dean Greer McKee, Howard Tillman Kuist (adjunct from Princeton Theological Seminary), and Edwin Lewis (adjunct from Drew Universi ty). Professor Traina excelled as a student at The Biblical Seminary , and the faculty, recognizing his extraordinary gifts, enco uraged him to serve the church as a teacher in theological education. Indeed, they hired him as a member of the faculty upon his graduation from seminary. During his early years of teaching at The Biblical Seminary, Professor Traina became troubled at the lack of integration between English Bible and traditional exegesis. He judged that English Bible, as it was being taught at The Biblical Seminary, was not as comprehensive and specific as was needed to teach Out of this concern, Professor Traina students effectively. expanded and sharpened the method of English Bible. He developed it into an organized and comprehensive approach,

4


5

combining the unique f ea tu res of the inductive method as it had been taught over the years with the insights and tools of traditional exegesis. Professor Traina set forth his approach to inductive Bible study in his book, Methodical Bible Study, published in 1952. This book, translated into several languages, has been used in scores of colleges and seminaries around the world , and has served as the basis for many other works on Bible study. Its sales have averaged 2,500 copies a year. It would be difficult to overestimate the effect this book has had on the Church. In the early 1960s, The Biblical Seminary in New York experienced a time of transition , resulting in a radical change in the nature of the seminary itself. At this time, Professor Traina concluded that he could best minister elsewhere; and in 1966, having just earned his Ph.D. from Drew University, he accepted an invitation to join the faculty of Asbury Theological Seminary as a professor of English Bible. After serving as academic dean and vice president for academic administration from 1967 to 1975, he resumed full-time teaching in English Bible, from which he will retire at the end of the academic year 1987-88. In addition to Methodical Bible Study, Professor Traina's scholarly contributions include two chapters in Interpreting God 's Word for Today : An Inquiry into Hermeneutics from a Biblical Theological Perspecti ve. vol 11, Warner Press, Anderson, IN, 1982, and articles in Baker's Dictionary of Christian Ethics, Baker Book House, Grand Rapids, MI, 1973, Christianity Today, and The Asbury S eminarian. He is currently engaged in writing a sequel to Methodical Bible Study. But Professor Traina's most enduring influence will no doubt be found in the lives and ministries of his students. The contributors to this issue of the Asbury Theological Journal have been chosen from among the most eminent of Professor Traina's teachers, colleagues and students. Dr. David L. McKenna, president of Asbury Theological Seminary, writes the tribute. Dr. William J. Abraham, a memeber of the faculty at Perkins School of Theology, Southern Methodist University, addresses the difficult issue of authorial intentionality in the interpretave process . Dr. Jerry H. Gill , associate professor of religious studies at the College of St. Rose in Albany, New York, and a widely recognized philosopher in his own right, contributes an article dealing with contemporary philosophical problems surrounding hermeneutics. Dr. Eugene Lemcio, professor of religion at Seattle Pacific University, explores the redaction of the "love commands" in the synoptic Gospels in the light of Pirke 'Abot 1:2(3). Dr. Donald G . Miller, who has served on the


6

faculties of The Biblical Seminary in New York, Union Theological Seminary in Virginia and as president of Pittsburgh Theological Seminary, and whose impressive career includes major works in biblical studies, theology and preaching, offers a challenging discussion of the New Testament concept of "witness ." Finally, Dr. Robert W. Lyon, professor of New Testament interpretation at Asbury Theological Seminary, looks again at the interpretation of a crucial passage in the Gospel of John. It is my hope that this issue will serve as a worthy tribute to one of the great teachers in the Church .

DAYID R. BAUER, Ptt.D . Guest Editor


Tribute to Robert A. Traina Teaching is a calling, a gift, a discipline and a ministry. When the Apostle Paul urged the Ephesians to live and work worthy of the particular grace which Christ Jesus had apportioned to them, he identified teachers as colleagues with apostles, prophets and evangelists and saw their common task, ... to prepare God's people for works of service, so that the body of Christ may be built up until we all reach unity in the faith and in the knowledge of the Son of god and become mature, attaining to the whole meas ure of the fullness of Christ (Ephesians 4: 11-13, NIV). Robert Traina answered the call of God to teach and accepted the gift of teaching as his lifetime ministry. Consequently, he stands among apostles, prophets and evangelists as a colleague in the common task of preparing "God's people for the works of service." I am only one among multitudes who can witness to the influence of Dr. Traina's teaching, which has not only built the Body of Christ in the unity of faith and knowledge but also nurtured our maturity toward the "whole measure of the fullness of Christ." Although I never took a class from Robert Traina, he is my teacher. As a young seminarian in the early 1950s, I had a thirst to know the Word of God . Survey courses in Bible had given me a "skimming knowledge" of the Word. Critical courses in Bible had given me a "needle knowledge" of the Word. Both were needed and valuable. But then I enrolled for my first course in English Bible, a study of the Book of Judges. Methodical Bible Study, by Robert Traina, served as our textbook. The course awakened me to the Word in a way that I shall never forget. After I learned the principles of inductive Bible study and applied them to the study of the Book of Judges, the Spirit of God broke through my study with an insight that was at once creative, inspired and practical. My mind raced and my spirit leaped as never before in a learning situation. For the first time, I knew what the Apostle Paul meant when he described the "unity of faith and knowledge" as an outcome of teaching. Throughout the night, I found myself waking up with the anticipation of sharing a biblical insight with my professor and fellow students. Naively, but honestly, I was convinced that I had discovered a truth in the Word of God that no one had ever seen before. Then and there, inductive Bible study became a lifetime commitment. Years later, as president of Seattle Pacific University, I learned that Robert Traina and his wife Jane were graduates of the school.

!

7


8

In the search for our most distinguished alumni, their nam es surfaced as two people whose lives and ministries exemplified the ideals of the Christian university. The circles of their influence were far wider than might be expected. Dr. Traina, as a professor at The Biblical Seminary in New York and then Asbury Theological Seminary, stood at the very center of the movement to bring English Bible into the heart of the seminary curriculum . Although the classical tradition of theological education and the critical tradition of biblical study militated against this more practical intrusion, the values of English Bible were spelled out in the responses of students whose preaching and teaching were measurably enhanced. They did not hesitate to say so. When the time came to nominate the Alumnus of the Year for 1978 at Seattle Pacific University, Robert Traina was named and selected. Together with Jane and the family, we honored him in the U niversity Chapel, the annual homecoming event, an alumni dinner and a community reception. Not without significance, the event stands out as highlight of celebrating the new status of Seattle Pacific as a "University." When I accepted the presidency of Asbury Theological Seminary in 1982, the Trainas and McKennas were joined togeth er again as colleagues in a new dimension of preparing God's people for works of service. Early on, I remember pass ing his classroom door and seeing his meticulous and penetrating outline on the ever-present overhead screen. When I asked students about their learning, they invariably mentioned the insights of Dr. Traina's classes for preaching value and spiritual growth. When the opportunity came to establish a new professorial chair in the Seminary, I had the privilege of presiding at the installation of Dr. Traina as the Fred M. and Ada Thompson Professor of Biblical Studies. Most notable for the occasion , Pat Robertson, the television evangelist and presidential candidate, came to give the installment address for Dr. Traina. As one of his students at The Biblical Seminary in New York, Robertson spoke the witness, " Dr. Traina brought the Word of God to life for me." More recently, we have seen the consecration of Robert Traina to his calling. Periodic bouts of physical illness ha ve sapped hi s strength. Yet, even if it has meant getting out of bed only for the hours of his classes, he has taught whenever it is humanl y possible. As a former dean of the Seminary, his preparation for teaching and his dedication to the classroom are exemplary for our faculty. Although Dr. Traina managed his own physical suffering, the dreaded cancer that took the life of his wife, Jane , caused him pain that seemed to know no limit. The brightness, bounce a nd


9

beauty which Jane exuded so naturally was taken from his life. Only his faith and family have sustained him during the time of grief. Outwardly, he has kept his composure, faithfully carried out his duties, and continued to minister to the others, but inwardly he weeps over his loss even while he cherishes the memories of life with Jane and claims the promise of eternal life. The "Jane Traina Bookstore" at the Seminary is a permanent memorial to her "counter ministry" with students, faculty, administration, book agents and visitors alike. Retirement is only another chapter in Dr. Traina's life history. His influence at the center of the English Bible movement will continue to spread in ever-widening circles wherever the gospel is preached. At the Seminary, his students who are now professors, Drs. David Thompson and David Bauer, are already rising in professorial, pastoral and scholarly stature to take his place. The revision of his Methodical Bible Study will continue to be a widely-used textbook that is timeless. Our Seminary curriculum gives required study in English Bible its rightful place among more classical courses. And, in the future, we envision the full endowment of the Professorial Chair of English Bible. Dr. Robert Traina, on behalf of the trustees, faculty and students of Asbury Theological Seminary, we thank God for you and celebrate your lasting ministry among us.

DA YID L. MCKENNA


!

10


Intentions and the Logic of Interpretation WILLIAM J. ABRAHAM What exactly are we doing when we say that an author's intentions should or should not have a role in the interpretation of a text? Are we making a claim about a crucial piece of evidence which should be taken into account, if at all poss ible? Or are we making a claim about grammar or logical character of the whole enterprise of interpretation? In this paper I shall mount a modest case for the latter way of construing this issue . I shall argue, that is, that the debate about intentions has been misplaced.I It has less to do with external avowals which an author may or may not make about the meaning of his work and much more to do with the fundamental goal of the interpretative process as a whole. We will begin by sketching more fully the first option and examining the case against appeal to intentions on that level. When an author's intentions in writing a particular text operate as a piece of external evidence, the logic of the situation is relatively straightforward. In puzzling over the meaning of a text, we normally assemble all sorts of evidence. We take into acco unt the genre, the grammar, the style, the literary context, the usus loquendi of the words used, the circumstances in which the text was written, how it may have bee n or was received in its day, how it may have been composed and put together over time , and the like. Alongside these we now place the author's own account of what he was doing in writing the text under review. According to our hypothetical theory, the author's avowals will be treated as decisive in the construal of the text. These avowals ma y themselves be expressed in a variety of ways. They may be written in diaries or workbooks; or they may have been enshrined in a commentary on the relevant work; or they may have been made in some kind of public or private utterance which has been written

William J. Abmham earned his M.Div. degree at Asbury Theological Seminary and his Ph.D. at Oxford University. He is McCrefess Associate Professor of Evangelism at Perkins Schoof of Theology, South em Methodist University.

VOL 43 No. 1

THE ASBURY THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

!

11

1988


12

Abraham

down and has Of course, the author's intentions ma y have been enshrined in the text itself. One thinks immediatel y of what Luke has to say in his famous prologue or what John says in his tantalizing comments towards the end of his gospel. But this is so rarely true that we can overlook it for the moment. In an y case, the appeal would be much the same: the author's avowals about his intentions would be treated as having a privileged position in the debate about the most appropriate rendering of the text. At the very least it would require very strong evidence to overturn what the author said he meant on any particular occasion. The appeal to intentions as evidence for a partic ular interpretation of a text has not, to my knowledge, been used to displace the appeal to other kinds of evidence. Othe r considerations are to be included in the process of interpretation; the issue is one of status, not exclusivism. Indeed, as applied to Holy Scripture the appeal to the intentions of the original author was embedded in a profound and hard-won attempt to tac kle questions about the meaning of a text in a rigo rous and intellectually persuasive manner. On the one hand, it was part of a move to cut texts loose from dogmatic, theological traditions which refused to let them speak for themselves. In earlier times the enemy tended to be the classical creeds of the Church , while in more recent times the great enemy has been real and imagined forms of Fundamentalism. On the other hand, it was an attempt to rid scholarship of faulty methods of interpretation--like allegory, or hasty, pietistic application--which imposed meanings on the text which were clearly not there in the first place. Several interesting assumptions about texts and about human action are built into this deliberately sketchy account of interpretation. It is assumed, for example, that texts and autho rs are not just contingently, but logically, connected . A text is demarcated from mere markings on paper by its conceptual relation to human action. Texts are in fact human , inte ntional actions. They are the expression of human purposes and intentions; they are not mere events which occur as the result of natural, Jaw - like happenings in the world; they embody and ma ke manifest human consciousness. It is also assumed that, although texts are actions of human subjects acting to express certa in intentions and purposes, they are also objects in the world and as such they possess an independence which stands over against the would-be interpreter. However difficult it may be to decipher or read them, texts must be approached with great patience and skill so that their authors may be heard and understood. They should not be railroaded into saying something which their authors did not intend them to say. Furthermore, it is assumed that the


Intentions and the Logic of lnte!pretation

13

author's intentions have a privileged position in the process of interpretation because the author has privileged access to his or her intentions. Generally speaking, the human subject knows his or her intentions better than an external observer does, or so it is widely held. It is this principle which surely operates as the warrant for the special place of authorial intention in the debate about interpretation. Finally, it is assumed in this account that we can draw a distinction between the meaning of a text and the significance of a text. The former remains stable; it is that which the author intended to convey in the text. To be sure, our account of what the author meant may have to change, for new evidence about authorial intention may come to light and hence lead to revisions in our interpretation. But that is one thing. It is another thing entirely to identify the significance of what a text says. Here we may speak of its truth or falsity, its depth or shallowness, its relevance or irrelevance, its beauty or plainness, and so on. These may change drastically, depending on the criteria of evaluation we deploy, on the circumstances in which we find ourselves and on the personal commitments of those making the evaluation. However we plot the distinction in detail, some distinction between meaning and significance will be pressed upon us by those who want to stress the crucial role of intentions in the act of interpretation. It is not entirely clear whether the attack on the role of intentions is meant to cut into all of the aforementioned assumptions. It may be simply an attack on the status of appeal to intentions when they are seen as part of wider battery of evidence which might be mustered by an interpreter. Or it may be something much more ontological and philosophical. It is absolutely crucial that we be clear about this, for there is far more to intentions than meets the eye initially.2 This is one of the enduring merits of attending to the claims of Derrida among the deconstructionists and Rorty among the new pragmatists.3 The latter are seeking to undermine in a very profound way the epistemological foundationalism which has been central to Western philosophy since Descartes. Their work in literary criticism generally, and their attack on intentionalism in particular, are part and parcel of a wider vision that covers issues which go far beyond those encompassed in traditional hermeneutics. An innovation of the magnitude they are seeking cannot hang on some kind of intentional fallacy, however generously construed; nor for that matter can it hinge on appeal to some expert in the field of literary criticism. Such an attack will depend on substantive philosophical moves in epistemology, and Rorty at least is only too aware of the demands that this lays upon both him and Derrida.


14

Abraham

Indeed, what both Rorty and Derrida want to do is to overturn philosophy and epistemology, yet to do so they must deploy recognizably philosophical arguments, a feat which no one has as yet successfully performed . So we do well to isolate the debate about intentions initially as a debate about the status of certain kinds of evidence in the interpretation of a text. It is not difficult to find fault with the appeal to intentions in the interpretation of a text, and ever since Wimsatt and Beardsley published their famous article on the "intentional fallacy," many have followed their lead in banishing intentions from the process of interpretation proper. 4 Their strictures about intention were initially limited to the interpretation of poetry, but as the debate proceeded they were extended to literature generally.s Of late, opposition to intentions has been spreading to biblical studies, most especially among those who are interested in the literary study of the Bible. It is surely not an exaggeration to say that a deep division has developed between those who operate fundamentally as historians and those who operate fundamentally as literary critics. Up ahead it is likely that the division will become sharper and deeper. The attack on intentions is mounted from a variety of angles. The most popular move at first is to point to the simple fact that in most cases, say, of the biblical literature, the author's intentions are not accessible. Like most simple points, this is expected to settle the issue immediately and its proponents hope to return in triumph to a closer reading of the text, trusting that they will be left alone to get on with their work. If this is all there is to the debate about intentions, then indeed the debate is over and we had best bury it for good. One could, of course, take the simple logical expedient of accepting the consequences of this state of affairs and arguing that this does not overthrow the place of intentions; it just shows that we are not in a position to interpret the relevant biblical material. Biblical scholars need not quit their jobs, but they must now earn a living performing other functions in the commonwealth of learning. That no one has seriously suggested this option should make us pause and ponder what is really at stake in the debate as a whole. Those opposed to intentions, however, are not going to be satisfied with this abrupt attempt to keep the commitment to intentions unharmed and intact. So the attack proceeds apace. Suppose we have access to the intentions of the author. For one thing, our author may have failed to execute her intentions in the work in question. Yet this does not render her text meaningless or necessarily obscure. Meaning therefore must be logically distinct form intentions. For another, the author may


Intentions and the Logic of Interpretation

15

have abandoned her original intentions in the course of her work or she may have included material which was not at all central in her deliberations. If the intentions have in any way changed, they can be of no help in determining the meaning of the work in hand. Moreover, there is no guarantee that the author best knows her intentions. We can all be deceived or ill-informed about our intentions. In some cases it even appears that the author had no idea what she was up to until the work was finished and she turned and read the work for herself, just like any other intelligent reader. Privileged access, even if it does exist, does not in the least guarantee infallibility; yet only infallibility could underwrite the claim that avowals about intentions have a special status. Add to this the fact that a text often has a surplus of meaning over and above what the author intended . Our author may not know the full meaning of what she is saying , or she may be incompetent or not inclined to declare what she meant. Surely something along these lines lies behind the commonplace among Protestants that God has still more light to break from His Word. The original author may have only been incipiently aware of what she was saying; to limit oneself to intentional meaning is therefore restrictive and spiritually debilitating. Texts are far richer than the standard intentionalist can allow. Furthermore, persons who talk about the intentions of an author tend to be general and schematic, so it is not clear how precisely they will illuminate this or that part of the text. An author's intention to write a satire or a tragedy does not tell the reader how to handle the details of the script. Indeed there are cases where knowledge of the author's intentions tells us next to nothing about the text. Thus, to know that someone wrote a play to make a lot of money or to placate an enemy will not get us very far in the process of interpretation. Nor can the appeal to intentions set any ultimate guard against subjectivity, as Hirsch and his admirers so fondly hope, for intentions are by definition inward mental acts which are not available for inspection by the general public. It is surely better by far to work with the text in hand and let its precise and particular features settle whatever disputes arise. Textual certainties may not amount to much when weighed in the scales of knowledge, but they are all we have and they are always to be preferred to biographical speculations which take us away from the text and into the swamps of endless background studies and genetic guesswork. Finally, there are extra considerations which come into play when we deal with a canonical text of Scripture. Text embodied in a sacred canon takes on new meaning when read as part of the canonical whole. As the biblical writers had no idea that their


16

Abraham

work would have canonical status, there is no way in which they could have intended the meaning that their work now has, given its place in Holy Scripture. Attempts to get around this by claiming that the intentions of the final editors or canonizers , or even God, are to be the bearers of the relevant intentions is just one last-ditch effort to save the appeal to intentions. There is absolutely no warrant in the texts themselves for such a move; only a dogged commitment to theory precipitates such desperate expedients. The consequences of this attack on intentions are extremely significant for hermeneutics. By far the most interesting for our purposes is that it calls into question the whole quest to ferret out the inner life behind the outer text associated with Schleiermacher, Dilthey and Collingwood. Thus, if this attempt to reject intentions succeeds, it will make no sense to speak of the interpreter reversing the causal process which brought the text into existence or of seeking to relive the thoughts which lie behind the text. Exercises of this character will be seen as adding nothing to the task of interpretation properly conceived; on the contrary, they may well be construed as a devious distraction. To be sure, such operations may be of some psychological value in drawing attention to evidence within the text which might otherwise go unnoticed, but they are of no deep epistemic value and they are assuredly not the heart of the interpretive enterprise . Those opposed to intentionalism of one sort or another are not agreed on exactly what the heart of the enterprise should be . Some, especially those impressed by Marx, have turned to the social context of a text, as the key to interpretation. How far this alternative can avoid an unacceptable form of determinism and reductionism cannot be pursued here, but there is no denying that placing texts in their wider social setting can be exceptionally illuminating and the wise interpreter will develop a keen eye for the possibilities which this option may make available. Others, especially those interested in the formal f ea tu res and structures of language, have turned to a close reading of the text as an autonomous object as the hope for the future. The text itself is read and reread until it yields up its riches. Again, there is no denying the fascinating and penetrating observations which have emerged from such endeavour. Others have sought for their literary salvation in the mining of continental, hermeneutical philosophy and the theories of meaning developed in this fertile domain. As some ponder the options, they sometimes gain the impression that the task of interpretation has become a thoroughly relativistic operation where subjectivism reigns and where there are no controls to adjudicate between one interpretation and


Intentions and the Logic of Interpretation

17

another. 1 suspect that this reaction reflects panic rather than good judgment, but, where sentiments like this prevail, it is small wonder that the commitment to intentions as a crucial issue in hermeneutics dies very hard indeed . If intentions are to be seen as crucial, however, it should not be because appeal to intentions is the only way to head off relativism or subjectivism. Taking this line, aside from tending to beg vital questions against rival visions of interpretation , is likely to breed fantasy and confusion in our hermeneutics . If intentions are important, it is not just because we want them to be important or because we fail to be attracted by anti-intentionalist or nonintentionalist accounts of interpretation. They should be taken seriously because reference to them is logically indispensable in any plausible account of interpretation. In recent analytical philosophy precisely such an account has emerged over the last generation. The account in question began !ife as an attempt to solve certain problems in the philosophy of language and was then applied to the debate about interpretation. Even though the primary work on this issue is highly technical, the relevant data for the task of interpretation can be stated quite succinctly. The key point to grasp is that the meaning of an utterance is not just a matter of the discourse deployed or the sentences uttered; it is fundamentally a matter of the speech act performed by the speaker on specific occasions in particular contexts. Moreover, the speech act performed is in turn determined by the intentions of the relevant speaker. Hence the interpretation of an utterance, and by extension the interpretation of a text, is logically related to the action performed by the person or persons who made the utterance or produced the text, and the action can only be identified by referring to the intention which governs it. The standard way to deal with the issue at stake here is to attend to what J. L. Austin referred to as the illocutionary force of an utterance. 6 Thus when someone in normal circumstances seriously utters the sentence, "Shut the door," there are three distinct elements to be noted. There is the locution itself or the locutionary act; the speaker has said this particular sentence. There is, secondly, the act performed in what has been said; in this case an order has been given. Finally, there is a perlocutionary element in that this particular act may have had certain effects on its hearer; say, it may have made the hearer feel sad. According to Austin and those who have borrowed or built on his work, understanding the illocutionary force of an utterance is essential to understanding the meaning of an utterance, hence it is quite inadequate simply to attend to the public meaning of the


18

Abraham

sentence uttered . Thus, to take a hackneyed example, if someone were to say, "There is thin ice over there," it is essential not only to know what the various parts of this sentence mean in English but also to know how the speaker is using the sentence. Normally we ta ke it as an affirmation, but in various circumstances this sentence could be an order, a warning, an insult or a request. To know this we need to know the intentions of the speaker in using this particular utterance. Discarding any reference to intentions and attending closely merely to the locutionary act in question will e liminate , therefore, an essential ingred ient in the meaning and hence in the understanding of the utterance. What applies to this short, pithy utterance also applies to whole stretches of utte rance such as we find in written texts. Needless to say, various aspects of this proposal have co me unde r attack in the philosophy of language .7 Enough of it remains intact, however , to cut deepl y into the d ebate about intentions. What is especially important is the general orientation which it gives to the interpretive process. Even if the case has not been fully made for intentions as the necessary and sufficient conditions for the identification of illocutionary force, it sets texts very firmly in the domain of human actions . So Dilthey and his admirers were correct to develop a general hermeneutic which would focus on the understanding of human actions generally as the key to understanding texts. A text is not so me abstract entity floating in free space endowed with meaning by some mystical agent called language or discourse. Nor are texts natural objects produced by passive, unintentional agents. Whatever else they are, texts are fundamentally the fru it of human action and are generally created to express human intentions and purposes. Speakers produce meaning, not texts per se; in this process they make use of discourse, and to reverse this order and focus primarily on language and secondarily on what is actually achieved by use of language is to get the cart before the ho rse. As Strawson puts it succinctly, " as theorists, we know nothing of human language unless we understand human speech." 8 Hence , when interpreters debate the role of intentions in their wo rk it is hope lessly inadequate to resolve this issue simply by insisting that we may not have access to the avowals of the author as to what he or she meant. To work on this level is to work bereft of crucial conceptual tools and thus prevent the relevant issues being canvassed appropriately from the outset of the discussion. Besides, making an avowal about our inte ntion is only one way of getting access to our intention, and we may be more or less fallible in our claims in this domain. The text itself will be a vital part of the evidence as to what intentions are expressed


Intentions and the Logic of Interpretation

19

in the work, and it is the task of the interpreter to develop skill in picking up what they are and hence determining what the force of the utterance under review may be. Nor will it do to confuse intentions with logically distinct matters such as motives, desires, feelings and other mental acts and events.9 To do so is to make elementary blunders in the philosophy of mind and breed unnecessary confusion in the field of hermeneutics. Yet we must be careful in all our claims about both human actions and intentions . The terrain here is extraordinarily slippery and it is easy to fall prey to simplistic theories of action. Contrary to the standard orthodoxy on the subject, I seriously doubt if a general theory of human action is in fact intellectually attainable. This is not to decry the attempt to tie actions to intentions conceptually, but I am not fully convinced that all that human agents do as responsible agents is done intentionally. It is certainly useful to begin with a firm connection between actions and intentions, but this is the first word; it is unlikely to be the last. Thus I may set out to do x and end up doing y without at all realizing what I was doing or intending to do what I did. For example, contemporary television evangelists insist that they are simply using modern media to spread the old-time gospel, while in actual fact many of them are offering a new gospel message and their actions are more akin to that of an entertainer than that of an evangelist. That they would vehemently reject such a description of their action is beside the point. They are simpl y unaware of the social character of their behavior and how it may be legitimately understood. If this example seems too controversial, consider the situation where I set out to shoot Murphy in the Enniskillen stockyard filled with cattle. I fire and miss, but my action of shooting scares the cattle and they stampede, trampling Murphy to death. Here I have the intention to kill Murphy and I kiII him, congratulating myself all the way to prison for what I have done; but I do not kill him intentionally . I suspect that examples like these may crop up quite frequently in our work on human texts, and anti-intentionalists are correct to focus on how tricky intentions really are. However, they tend to misread the significance of their astute observations by failing to see this as a signal to look afresh at the whole notion of action rather than as an invitation to focus on texts in themselves. We need to pursue the complexity of human speech - acts rather than just look again at the language and text. This is what I meant at the outset of this paper when I suggested that the debate about intentions was misplaced; it is less a matter of the relevance of certain kinds of evidence than it is about the total orientation of our work in hermeneutics. It is crucial in this orientation to place


20

Abraham

texts where they belong; in the stream of human life, thought and action. We might summarize the fundamental thesis we are driving towards in this wa y: Hermeneutics is not so much the stud y of what an author intended as the study of what the author achieved. If meaning has an equivalence, it is to be located less in intention and more in achievement. What is achieved may be more o r less than what the author intended; happily we can be generous and charitable in our initial judgments and trust that intention and achievement may coincide more often that not. In an y case, the old proverb holds; actions speak louder than words; so it is the actions which should get our full attention. Moreover, in understanding actions we do well to adopt the lofty vision outlined by Dilthey: " The ultimate goal of the hermeneutic process is to understand an author better than he understood himse lf." 10 This is clearl y the case with many human actions, and thus we do well to set ourselves this task in hermeneutics. In the light of this, the task of the interpreter is to summon all the relevant evidence and all the ski ll that can be mustered to elucidate the nature of the achievement in question . For the author, the road to mea ning is paved by good achievements, and the versatile and wily interpreter will map out such achievements as lucidly as possible. In constructing such maps, it will be useful to bear the following general rubrics in mind (all of which stem from construing a text as an achievement or an action and all of which have been vigorously advocated at one time or another in the history of hermeneutics). First, it is useful to keep a distinction between the elucidation of a text and the evaluation of a text. As with the evaluatio n of actions generally, it is morally required that we know what a person has done in some detail before we evaluate the worth of what has been done. This holds for the study of action in the writing of texts. In the evaluation of a text, it is important a t times to bear in mind the intended aim of the author. For example, if a writer intended to write a satire or an apocalypse, it is clearly erroneous to evaluate such work as if it were a piece of sober historical narrative . Intention in itself does not determine, in some simplistic fashion, precisely what value we should attach to a particular work, but it should be taken into account in the evaluative process overall. We may even need to take into account the motives of an author as we evaluate a text. Thus, if we know that a writer's motive was to smear the good name of an opponent, then this will have an obvious bearing on our val ue of the worth of the text. The process of evaluation as a whole will involve a variety of criteria, depending on our commitments and


Intentions and the Logic of Intetpretation

21

the express point of our evaluations. The good interpreter will develop a high degree of self knowledge in this area without sacrificing nimbleness of touch and economy of operation. Second, in elucidating a text, it will be crucial to attend to the linguistic repertoire of an author. The study of grammar, syntax, vocabulary, genre, style, local idioms, usage, and the like, are indispensable. In this there is no substitute for the demanding task of mastering the original languages. The loss of these in the modern seminary is surely to be deeply regretted. Also crucial is a knowledge of how to read a book as a whole, dismantle it and then put it back together again . Here concessions to the natural language of the reader can legitimately be made, and it is crucial to bear in mind the communicative conventions Traina has captured in his analysis of the relationships to be found with a text. 11 We need also to bear in mind the innovations and transformations which an author may have introduced. In all, we need to know the capacities and range of options available to an author in producing a text. If we neglect this, we are liable to underestimate or overestimate what has been , or fail to perceive what action has actually been performed . Third, we need to develop a keen eye for the historical context and particular circumstances in which a text has been written. At this point, the current wrangle between historians and literary critics is of deep significance. It is certainly true that historians have not always served us as well as they might. As far as the interpretation of Scripture is concerned, they have at times dismantled the texts into atomistic bits and pieces, they have lost the text in a mass of genetic and background information, they have indulged in fanciful speculation which is intellectually unedifying, they have set unduly restrictive limits on the options open to the contemporary theologian, and they have arrogantly set aside exegetical insights from the astonishingly rich heritage of interpretation which is available to us. Whatever catalogue of sins we cobble together, we cannot ignore history if we construe the interpretation of a text as the interpretation of a human achievement. Achievements take place in a context and in a set of circumstances. To understand them is to see them as making sense within the conventions, assumptions, values, beliefs and attitudes of their situation. Hence our knowledge of an author's repertoire of linguistic action depends on historical information about the period and the circumstances of the actual writing. Those who focus on a close reading of the text as an autonomous object

either ignore this at their peril or smuggle precisely such information into the interpretive process without acknowledgment. There is another reason why history is important. Some texts


22

Abraham

cannot be understood at all adequately if we do not know something about the ideas and the events concerning which they speak. If we read a text ahistorically in such circumstances we are liable to go astray. Equally, if a writer is making a rejoinder to another text, it is important that we have access to such information. Thus, if an interpreter insists that Job is a response to Deuteronomy, or that James is a response to Paul, we need the aid of the historian in evaluating such claims. How we resolve these issues will have a clear bearing on the illocutionary force of much of what is said. We cannot say in advance when or how historical information will be relevant. Some texts are more heteronomous than others, but even in seemingly autonomous books like Proverbs it is exceptionally illuminating to have some idea of the proverbial repertoire available at the time of writing, the traditions out of which the book emerges, and the way in which the current text of Proverbs may represent or depart from these conventions. Of course our judgments in history are invariably contested , and it is easy to be carried away by those alternatives which chime with our prepossessions. The sensitive interpreter will soon learn to make a virtue of such necessities while taking with radical seriousness the canons of historical judgment. It is in this context that we should deal with the place of a text within the canon of Scripture as a whole . Two points deserve mention. First, it is both important and useful to see what happens to our understanding of a text when it has been placed in a sacred canon by a community of faith . It is best to designate our intellectual undertakings at this level not as the elucidation of the text but as the careful integration of the content of a variety of texts in a wider theological vision. When we appropriate the significance of a text of Scripture and relate it intimately to our expanding metaphysical commitments, how we do so will depend in part on how we relate that text to our understanding of other relevant, scriptural texts. Significance, in turn , will depend o n elucidation in the sense that we cannot satisfactorily gauge the value of a text without first knowing what the text means. He nce we need to tread warily when claims are made about the canonical meaning of a text. Perhaps we should speak of canonical significance rather than canonical meaning . Second, when we deal with the text as part of the canon of Scripture much more attention needs to be given to the broader historical considerations which are at stake. The process of canonization was part of a wider enterprise which the early church initiated in order to deal with its life and teachings in the crises which it faced over several centuries. Thus to cope with its


Intentions and the Logic of Interpretation

23

problems, the church not only put together a canon of Scripture, it also developed various creeds and put episcopacy in place. On an intellectual level, there is a deep sense in which creed and Scripture go together canonically, while episcopacy can be read as an attempt to secure these canons as integral to the social authority of the church and as constitutive of its identity. Much harm has been done in Protestantism when this is neglected. Scripture has been called upon to perform functions which were designed to be met by the creeds, and the creeds have been ignored or neglected in the canonical construal of Scripture. A canonical reading of Scripture which fails to take into account the early creeds of the church is therefore historically inept, and this is one more reason for treating the canonical interpretation of Scripture at the level of significance and appropriation rather than at the level of elucidation and exegesis. In conclusion , one further point springs naturally to mind in our brief comments on the rubrics of interpretation. When we deal with a text, we cannot ignore the subject or particular content in which the writer is engaged. To take a simple example, adequate elucidation of a classical philosophical text depends in part on one's capacity to understand philosophical ideas and issues. The good interpreter will be able to draw on insights which have been furnished by wrestling with the questions the text addresses and with rival ways of construing and resolving them. Initially, one's capacity in this field may well develop by means of extensive interaction and dialogue with the text in hand . More appropriately, we might say that our reading of a text is like a dialogue with an author or speaker whose action continues across space and time into the present to inform and develop our judgments and latent human capacities. This is clearly the case with Scripture. Deep and profound elucidations of the text depend on spiritual insight and on theological sensitivity as well as on standard linguistic, literary and historical skill. This is as it should be if the interpretation of a text is the interpretation of a human achievement, for this is inevitably set in the stream of human life, thought and action. Out of the richness of their experience, the depths of their theological acumen, the storehouse of their ability to communicate their proposals, the great interpreters take the reader into a new world of wonder and challenge where fresh horizons are encountered and prevailing capacities are developed. It is impossible to capture what is at stake here in a set of formal rules or in conceptual analysis of the underlying assumptions and principles. These have their place, but they are no substitute for direct exposure to those who have already mastered this art and


24

Abraham

can share it with others. In this respect it is difficult to surpass what Robert Traina instantiates for those fortunate enough to have 路 been his students.

Notes 1. There is a wealth of literature on the topic of intentio ns and their role in hermeneutics. Aside from the literature referred to in these notes, I have found the following material very helpful in preparing this foray into the debate abou t intentions: William E. Cain, The Crisis in Criticism (Baltimore and London: The Jo hn Hopkins University Press, 1984), chap. 1; Suresh Ravel, Metacn.ticism (Athens: The University of Georgia Press, 1981), chap. 3; Geoffrey Thurley, Counter-Modernism in Current Cn'tical Theory (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1983), chap. 7; K. K. Ruthven, Critical Assumptions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), chap. 9; Susan R. Horton, Interpreting Interpreting (Baltimo re and London: The Johns H opkins University Press, 1979), chap. 8; P. D. Juhl, Interpretation (Princeton: Princeton University P ress, 1980); E. D. Hirsch, The Aims of Interpretation (Chicago: C hicago University Press, 1976); David Newton-de Molina, On Literary Intention (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1976); Gora n Hermeren, "Intention and Interpretatio n in Literary Criticism," New Literary History, 7 (1975-76): 57-82; and Michael Hancher, "Three Kinds of Intention," Modem Language Notes, 87 (1972): 827-851. E specially iUuminating are the following articles by Quentin Skinner; "Meaning a nd Understanding in the History of Ideas," History and Th eory, 8 (1969): 3-53; "Conventions and the Understanding of Speech Acts," Philosophical Qua11erly, 20 ( 1970): 118-138; "On Perfo rming and Explaining Linguistic Action," Philosophical Qual1erly, 21 (1971): 1-21; "Motives, Intentions and the Interpretation of T exts," New Literary History, 3 (1971-72): 393-408; and "Hermeneutics and the Role of History," New Literary History, 7 (1975): 209-232. An outstanding discussion of mea ning with special reference to the meaning of metaphor is fo und in Janet M art in Soskice's, Metaphor and Religious Language (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985).

2. A very useful introductio n to the concept of intention can be found in J ack W. Melland, The Nature of Intention (London: Methuen, 1970). 3. See Richard Rorty, " Philosophy without Principles," in Against The01y, Literaty Studies and the New Pragmatism, ed. W. J . T. Mitchell (Chicago and London: C hicago University Press, 1985), pp. 132-138. 4. William K. Wimsatt and Monroe C. Beardsley, "The Intentional Fallacy," The Verbal Icon: Studies in the Meaning of Poetry (Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 1954). See also William K. Wimsatt, "Genesis: A Fallacy Revisited," in The Discipline of Criticism: Essays in Literary Theory, Interpretation, and History, ed. P. Demetz, et al. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1968), pp. 193-225. An excelle nt critique of Wimsatt and Beardsley can be found in Colin Lyas's, " Personal Qua lities and t he Intentional Fallacy," in vol. 6 of Philosophy and the Ans, The Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures (New York: St. M artin's Press, 1973), pp. 194-210.


Intentions and the Logic of Interpretation

25

5. This is surely correct in principle for, although there are significant differences between poetry and prose, it is clear that one can perform similar speech-acts in poetry as one normally does in prose. 6. J. L. Austin, Ho w to do Things with Words, ed. J . 0. Urmson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962). See also: John R. Searle, Speech A cts (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), Expression and Meaning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), Intentionality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983); H. P. Grice, "Utterer's Meaning, Sentence-Meaning and Word-Meaning," in J. R. Searle, ed., The Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971), pp. 54-70; P. F. Strawson, "Intention and Convention in Speech Acts," in J. R. Searle, ed., The Philosophy of Language; Stephen R. Schiffer, Meaning (Oxford: Clarendon Press,

1972). 7. Sec Max Black, "Meaning and Intention: an Examination of Gricc's Views," New Literary History, 4 (1973): 257-279. 8. P. F. Strawson, "Meaning and Truth," in Logico-Linguistic Papers (London: Methuen, 1971), p. 189. Emphasis as in the original. 9. Richard Palmer makes this mistake in his Henneneutics: Interpretation The01y in Schleiemwcher, Dilthey, lleidegger, and Gadamer (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1969), pp. 246-247.

10. Wilhelm Dilthey, "The Rise of Hermeneutics," New Literary History, 3 (1971-72): 244. 11. Sec Robert A. Traina, Methodical Bible Study (Wilmore, Kentucky: Private Publisher, 1952), pp. 57-59.



Mediated Meaning: A Contextualist Approach to Hermeneutical Method JERRYH. GILL Traditionally defined as "the science of interpretation ," hermeneutics has of late evolved into a full-fledged philosophical concern of its own. Flowing out of the two opposing branches of the early twentieth century's " search for meaning" (analytic and existentialist philosophy), hermeneutics stands today as the central intersection of dialogue within and among such diverse disciplines as philosophy, linguistics, the arts, political theory, psychology and theology. The issues and points of view are many and diverse.' My purpose here is to sketch, in broad strokes, the main contours of the landscape and to provide a suggested perspective or "inscape" of my own . The modern era of hermeneutical understanding was ushered in with the introduction of the historical-critical method of textual interpretation.2 In a much needed and eventually successful attempt to counteract the tyrannical dominance of authoritarian and/ or spiritualizing hermeneutical activity, modern scholarship turned to objective, scientific criteria and procedures for determining what a given text meant . I stress the past tense of the term "meant" advisedly, for the emphasis of the historicalcritical approach has consistently been on ascertaining what the text meant for the writer and those to whom it was originally addressed. By means of historical and textual research , including and especially archeological investigation, modern interpreters have sought to bridge the gap between the time of the text and their own, thereby facilitating a contemporary understanding of the text's meaning. Norman Perrin offers a fair account of this historical-critical method in the following passage: Jeny H. Gill, Ph.D., is associate professor ofreligious studies at the College of St. Rose, in Albany, New York.

THE ASBURY THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

VOL. 43 No. 1

1988


28

Gill

In the case of texts from another time and another culture this can be an extremely complex and difficult task , involving many different considerations, but the theoretical principles involved are both firmly established and well understood. We need, further, to understand as far as we can the intent of the author in writing the text, and the meaning understood by those for whom the text was written. For all of this we need a number of different critical skills, and ultimately a measure of historical imagination, as we seek to understand the text as the author intended it to be understood, or as it was understood by those who first read it.3 Over against what they perceived as the dehumanizing effects of the "cult of objectivity" existentialist thinkers arose, ad vocating a more personal, subjective approach to hermeneutics. 4 Not only is there no way to know the original meaning of a given text , since, as Kierkegaard demonstrated, "significant" meaning always transcends mere probability and observation, there is no need to know it, since what really matters for us is what the text means for today, here and now. In spite of their antipathy for each other, those advocating the historical-critical method and those touting the existentialist posture are agreed that there is a meaning to be found in the text, a message or lesson which can be discerned, either after appropriate scientific investigation , in the former case, or after proper demythologization, in the latter case. Bultmann is as clear as he is adamant that the meaning of biblical texts, for instance, must and can lie only in the fresh "self-understanding" which it brings to each of us. As he puts it: The real purpose of myth is not to present an objecti ve picture of himself in the world in which he lives. Myth should be interpreted not cosmologically, but anthropologically, or better still, existentially. Myth speaks of the power or the powers which man supposes he experiences as the ground and limit of his world and of his own activity and suffering. He describes these powers in terms derived from the visible world, with its tangible objects and forces, and from human life, with its feelings, motives, and potentialities ... Hence the importance of the New Testament mythology lies not in his imagery, but in the understanding of existence which it enshrines.5 Following along in the subjectivist mode, and drawin g as well


Mediated Meaning: A Contextualist Approach to Henneneutica/ Meth od

29

on the advice of the "new critics" to avoid the fallacy of assuming anyone can determine the writer's original intentions, the robust deconstructionists burst on the scene.6 This hermeneutical posture or non- posture maintains that the meaning of any text is what we make it, because not only are we unable to reconstruct its original meaning , either for the author or the readers, but language itself is incorrigibly vague, ambiguous and contradictory. The meaning of a text can never be ascertained and / or interpreted, either for those then or for us now, for the simple reason that language will not stand still long enough to allow a single meaning--and this fact ought to be celebrated, rather than lame nted! Any given statement can be given a number of meanings, sometimes even the opposite of what it appears to mean, as ironic utterances clearly illustrate. One of the more enthusiastic proponents of the application of this methodology to the theological enterprise is Mark Taylor. In personal conversation he said to me that it is "the most important thing to happe n to theology in the latter half of the twentieth century." It is significant to note that the decons tructionist hermeneutical posture, while sharing the subjectivist emphasis of the existentialist approach, differs both from it and from the objectivism of the historical-critical perspecti ve by insisting that meaning is never direct, but is, rathe r, entirely a function of the hearer's interpretive response. In other words, according to deconstructionist thinkers, the focus of meaning has shifted from the author, to the text itself, and finally to the reade r alone . In s hort, the activity of interpretation, as well as the meaning of a given text, has now become so indirect, the focus has become so "soft," as to be essentially nonexistent. Meaning is in the mind of the reader or hearer, period. It is, of course, impossible to de ny both the strengths and weaknesses of each of these hermeneutical postures. The trick is to devise some way of integrating the former and avoiding the latter without ending up with a lumpy eclecticism. Is there a way to maintain the objectivity and authority of the text, together with contemporary and personal relevance, and yet acknowledge the indirect , open- texture of language? By itself the histo rical-critical method is limited , both in results and scope of application. Existentialist hermeneutics tends to be not only a-historical but anti-historical and social. Deconstructionism makes a valuable point, but becomes pointless--and indeed, meaningless--when applied to itself. So, one must ask, in Peggy Lee's words, "Is that all there is?" My own suggestion at this juncture is to urge the development of a contextua/ist approach to hermeneutics, one which


30

Gill

incorporates the emphases and concerns at each of the above postures. More specifically, a contextualist hermeneutic seeks an understanding of a text in which meaning is mediated in and through the historical, existential and linguistic dimensions of human experience simultaneously. There simply is no need to choose any of these aspects of our common life as the primary mode, or to assume that they are mutually exclusive . For, clearly, our day-to-day existence does not come compartmentalized in such a manner. The following diagram indicates the relationship amongst these various emphases and methodologies:

Existentialist Method

Subjectivity

direct specific

Objectivity Historical-Critical .._ Cognitive Method

Deconstructionist Method

indirect open-texture

Contextualist Method

As I see it, contextualist hermeneutic is comprised of at least three main themes, each of which deserves a brief explication. The following remarks constitute my own "inscape" (with thanks to Gerard Manley Hopkins) into the hermeneutical thicket sketched above. II First, a contextualized perspective acknowledges the deeply social and relational character of language and speech. People speak, not only in order to be understood, but because they are understood. It is language which mediates social reality to us, both initially and continuously, and which brings us into the human community, both as members and as selves . Thus the hermeneutical task is surely grounded in a basic knowledge of


Mediated Meaning: A Contextualist Approach to Hermeneutica/ Method

31

what a given text meant in its original human context, both historically and linguistically. This historical-critical concern is complemented, rather than set aside, by an equally sincere concern for the meaning of a text in the contemporary setting. Moreover, neither of these dimensions is obviated by a sensitivity to the flexible, open-textured quality of language, a quality which is necessitated by the ever-evolving social tasks in which language is employed. One thinker who has contributed a great deal to this contextualist perspective is the social psychologist George Herbert Mead .7 Mead stressed the social character of the human self, and the crucial role played by language in the composition of both culture and personhood. He termed the process by means of which both are constituted, " symbolic interaction," and he argued cogently for the "thick" understanding of the integral relationship between language and reality which comprises the fabric of human existence. Language is more than a mere system of signs for designating parts and aspects of the world . It is, rather, an organic form of human behavior that creates and shapes our world as well as describing it. Here is how he states it: The central factor in such adjustment is "meaning." Meaning arises and lies within the field of the relation between the gesture of a given human organism and the subsequent behavior of this organism as indicated to another human organism by that gesture. If that gesture does so indicate to another organism the subsequent (or resultant) behavior of the given organism, then it has meaning . In other words, the relationship between a given stimulus--as a gesture--and the later phases of the social act for which it is an early (if not the initial) phase constitutes the field within which meaning originates and exists. Meaning is thus a development of something objectively there as a relation between certain phases of the social act; it is not a psychical addition to that act and it is not an "idea" as traditionally conceived .... The social process, as involving communication, is in a sense responsible for the appearance of new objects in the field of experience of the individual organisms implicated in that process. Organic processes or responses in a sense constitute the objects to which they are responses; that is to say, any given biological organism is in a way responsible for the existence (the meanings they have for it) of the objects to which it physiologically and chemically responds. There would, for example, be no food--no


32

Gill

edible objects--if there were no organisms which could digest it. And similarly, the social process in a sense constitutes the objects to which it responds or to which it is an adjustment. That is to say, objects are constituted in terms of meanings within the social process of experience and behavior through the mutual adjustment to one another of the responses or actions of the various individual organisms involved in that process, an adjustment made possible by means of a communication which takes the form of a conversation gestures in the earlier evolutionary stages of that process and of language in its later stages. s Another contributor to the contextualist approach is the mature Ludwig Wittgenstein.9 He emphasized the social and acti ve dimension of speech by likening it to the various "games people play ." He did not intend thereby to trivialize or demean linguistic interchange. Rather, he sought to highlight its pragmatic nature, that it is grounded in our shared tasks and purposes, and thus that it is a way we do things in and with our common world. Wittgenstein likened speech to a toolbox, to chess and to the exchange of money in order to suggest that meaning is, at the deepest level, a function of use in context. After all , apart from some concrete use in a particular setting by and to a specific person(s), a given string of sounds and/ or markings cannot be said to have any meaning at all. The following is a representati ve Wittgenstienian insight: You say: the point isn't the word, but its meaning, and yo u think of the meaning as a thing of the same kind as the word , though also different from the word. Here the word, there the meaning. The money, and the cow that you can buy with it. (But contrast: money, and its use .) ... A main source of our failure to understand is that we do not command a clear view of the use of our words. Our grammar is lacking in this sort of perspicuity. A perspicuous representation produces just that understanding which consists in "seeing connexions" .... 10 Hans-George Gadameru has also contributed to a contextualist understanding of hermeneutics by means of his explorations in the phenomenology of language. Like Wittengenstein , Gadamer focuses on the participatory and interactionary aspects of linguistic communication, particularly through the notions of "pla y" and "conversation." These notions underline both the creati ve and


Mediated Meaning: A Contextualist Approach to J-lenneneutical Method

33

dialogical character of speech, indeed, even to the point of stressing the significance of silence in an overall understanding of meaning. For Gadamer, language is organic; it grows and dies. In addition, language is neither optional nor arbitrary; all humans participate in it to some degree and, at the primordial level, it arises in the warp and weft of concrete daily existence. As he says: Language is by no means simply an instrument, a tool. For it is in the nature of the tool that we master its use, which is to say we take it in hand and lay it aside when it has done its service . That is not the same as when we take the words of a language, lying ready in the mouth, and with their use let them sink back into the general store of words over which we dispose. Such an analogy is false because we never find ourselves as consciousness over against the world and , as it were grasp after a tool of understanding in a wordless condition. Rather, in all our knowledge of ourselves and in all knowledge of the world, we are always already encompassed by the language that is our own. We grow up, and we become acquainted with men and in the last analysis with ourselves when we learn to speak. Learning to speak does not mean learning to use a preexistent tool for designating a world already somehow familiar to us; it means acquiring a familiarity and acquaintance with the world itself and how it confronts us.12 III A second motif of a contextualist hermeneutic is an insistence on the active and pragmatic character of linguistic communication. Here again, the later Wittgenstein's work has proven to be most helpful, for it gave rise to the insights of the Oxford philosopher , J. L. Austin.n Austin began by noting that frequently we do more than merely speak when we use language, we sometimes accomplish deeds as well. When, for example, we say "I apologize," or "I pronounce you husband and wife" in the appropriate circumstances, etc., we are performing the act of apologizing and pronouncing. Austin dubbed such utterances "performatives," and he suggested that as an important form of speech they break down the traditional dichotomies between language and reality, and between factual judgments and value judgments. In his later work, Austin suggested that every "speech-act" consists of at least three dimensions of meaning, each of which is essential to its overall significance.


34

Gill

Take, for example, the sign which used to hang in British railwa y lavatories: "Gentlemen Lift the Seat." One might well ask whether this is a stipulative definition, an empirical description, an imperative or an invitation to upperclass larceny. Everything depends on context and use, and in spite of the fact that it is both enlightening and entertaining to play around with possible meanings, it is roughly clear what this sign means. However, Austin would surely suggest that there is a "referential" dimension to the utterance (there must be gentlemen and a seat, for instance) , as well as an "intentional" dimension (what the sign-makers intended) and a "responsive" dimension (some signs are so constructed as to give rise to unintended responses). All of these aspects of meaning must be taken into consideration when interpreting the sign. It is this pragmatic thrust of language which counteracts the unbridled relativism of deconstructionism. For, although any given statement is subject to a wide variety of readings , in the vast majority of cases the context either provides sufficient guidance by which to ascertain the meaning, or sufficient feedback by which to determine what went wrong in the case of misunderstanding. To acknowledge the possibility of multiple meanings and misunderstandings is a far cry from affirming that concrete interpretation is impossible. As Wittgenstein put it: " If I say 'The ground was quite covered with plants,' do you want to say that you don't know what I mean until I give you a definition of a 'plant'?" Of course, many readings are possible, even here , but that does not mean that some are not better than others. 14 Another thinker, once again a phenomenologist, who f eeds into the pragmatist current of a contextualist approach to hermeneutics is Maurice Merleau-Ponty.15 His work on the pivotal role of human embodiment in the composition of our particular form of !ife, especially as it involves the use of speech as a form of bodily behavior, is of front-rank significance . Merleau-Ponty suggests that through embodiment and language we interact with and shape our world, both physical and social. In short, he contends that our world is in large measure linguistically constituted by means of our interaction with each other in our common environment for specific shared tasks. We can neither separate our "inner" selves from our interactional relationships with the world, nor can we grasp reality and/ or its meaning directly, apart from these relationships. However, reflection can "set back ... to watch the forms of transcendence fly up like sparks from a fire; it slackens the intentional threads which attach us to the world and thus brings them to notice."16


Mediated Meaning: A Conte.xtualist Approach to Henneneutical Method

35

IV Third, a contextualist stance toward hermeneutical activity recognizes that, at the primordial level, language and meaning are fundamentally m etaphoric in nature. The work of Owen Barfield is highly significant here.17 He calls attention to a deep contradiction which underlies our modern view of language. On the one hand , we are generally committed to the idea that people in ancient and classical (not to say "primitive") times imbibed myth and metaphor, while we in modern times have " put away such childish things" in favor of more precise, scientific speech. On the other hand, we are equally committed to a theory of language which entails that it begins with specific, literal meanings and only later are metaphoric and symbolic meanings derived. But both cannot be true. It cannot be the case that metaphors build on literal meanings and that the vast majority of literal terms are in fact "dead" metaphors! Barfie ld argues that at its inception, whether with respect to the species or the individual, language must be endemically poetic in the sense that it does not stand over against or represent reality, but rather functions symbiotically with it in the mutual composition of our experienced and known world. Primordial speech unites thought and reality, analytic speech divides them. Both, of course, are necessary to human life, but it is clear that the unity must exist, as a Gestalt, be/ore analysis can take place. Thus both the historical-critical method and deconstructionism must acknowledge a more fundamental level of meaning that provides the context or the foothold for their own activity to have meaning. We can only analyze, we can only deconstruct, what we have understood as meaningful in the first place. One of the most controversial books in philosophical circles in recent years has been Thomas Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. is Kuhn's insights into the development of scientific thought lend support to the case for a contextualist hermeneutic. In brief, he contends that in order for any scientific activity to be carried out there must exist some theoretic framework, some unarticulated assumptions, forming what Kuhn calls the dominant paradigm, according to which this activity, including the theoretic level, gets its direction and meaning. He also maintains that at certain crucial junctures in the histor y of science, these paradigms shift, causing a revolution in the way scientists think and work. The Copernican and Einsteinian revolutions are examples of such shifts in paradigms. What is pivotal for our topic is the idea, espoused by an increasing number of scientific thinkers, that all meaningful activity and thought must take place within some social and


36

Gill

linguistic context. Contrary to the warnings of some, this does not mean that all truth and meaning are relative in the subjectivist, skeptical sense. Rather, it simply means that serious attention must be paid to the shape and direction, to the concrete particulars, of the context within which linguistic meaning arises when one engages in the task of interpretation. From the fact that no meaning is contextless it does not follow that meaningful communication is impossible. There are many points of connection between the notion of paradigm and that of metaphor in the primordial sense. It is within what Stephen Pepper called our "root metaphors" l9 that we live and move and have our being, at both the practical and theoretic levels of our common human existence. One could argue that the history of any culture, especially in relation to intercultural encounter and dialogue, exhibits shifts in root metaphors, or mythologies, parallel to the paradigm s hifts in scientific thought. It is essential that hermeneutical activity be sensitive to and make constructive use of the differences and developments within and among various historical and cultural contexts. 20 One other important thinker whose work supports a metaphorical understanding of the contextualist approach to hermeneutics is the Harvard philosopher, Nelson Goodman. In his delightfully deep little book, Ways of World making , 21 Goodman invites us to think of the various worlds we inhabit, such as the worlds of science, economics, art, religion, morality, etc. , as the result of our collaborative, creative interaction with our multidimensional environment. They grow out of each other, overlap with each other, and at times conflict with each other. These worlds are not fabricated arbitrarily, but arise as we engage in various shared activities and purposes. Nevertheless, they develop organically out of basic alternative ways of conceptualizing reality. This sort of open-mindedness entails, to be sure, a kind of relativism, but Goodman insists that this does not mean "anything goes." He advocates a "relativism with rigor" in order to distinguish truly helpful root metaphors fro m wildeyed word salad. In his own words: What I have said so far plainly points to a radical relativism; but severe restraints are imposed. Willingness to accept countless alternative true or right world-versions does not mean that everything goes, that tall stories are as good as short ones, that truths are no longer distinguished from falsehoods, but only that truths must be otherwise conceived than as correspondence with a ready- made


Mediated Meaning: A Contextualist Approach to Henneneutical Method

37

world . Though we make worlds by making versions, we no more make a world by putting symbols together at random than a carpenter makes a chair by putting pieces of wood together at random. The multiple worlds I countenance are just the actual worlds made by and answering to true or right versions. Worlds possible or impossible supposedly answering to false versions have no place in my philosophy.22

v What, then, are the potential dividends for religious life and understanding of this contextualist hermeneutical stance? Clearly such an approach entails a mediational view of revelation. By this I mean a view which sees God's activity in the world as mediated in and through historical, social and natural processes and events. For the Christian faith the notion of incarnation focuses this understanding of revelation in an axial fashion. "The Word became flesh and dwelt among us, and we beheld the glory,. .. full of grace and truth." The emphasis here is on discerned glory amidst the significant dimensions of life , not on supernatural intrusions from outer space. Even and especially in Christ we see through a glass, darkly. I say "especially" because it is only by means of a mediated mode of revelation that God can embody and communicate honest love and respect for human decision and responsibility, as John Hick has so profoundly made clear.23 A contextualist hermeneutic will come at the S criptures in a similar manner. As a most important mediator of the nature and meaning of divine revelation, the texts of the Bible must be interpreted in terms of every relevant dimension: historically, literarily, culturally, existentially and imaginatively. What the y meant originally, as best as can be determined , what they have meant through the centuries, what they mean to us now, and what they may mean to readers now and in the future--all these contexts mediate significant meaning, even for one another. The focus should be on the various root metaphors in each context and on how they function for the people therein, always with an eye to what they may yet reveal in our own and other settings. The Scripture is a record and interpretation of the community of believers' interaction with what they discern as God's activity in their midst. Two examples come readily to mind. Martin Luther King's interpretation of Israel's approach to the "Promised Land" in relation to the cause of Black people in America and the Civil Rights Movement was more than mere application, while being less specific than simple allegory. It constitutes an exemplary case of contextualist methodology. In a similar vein, the Reformist


38

Gill

dimension of the Christian Feminist Movement constitutes, in my view, a sound contextualist interpretation of Paul's powerful, if belatedly understood , remark that "In Christ there is ... no male or female" (Galatians 3:28). The true meaning of this remark has only begun to dawn on the Christian Church. The symbolism and ritual of worship will also be seen in a different light as a result of a contextualist hermeneutic. Participation in traditional and / or contemporary worship need not be viewed as merely that, but can be appreciated as a mediational means of participating in a multidimensional reality, wherein significance and value arise through active commitment to and involvement with the people and events of one's context. Baptism, the saying of the creeds, and the Eucharist, for example, are activities we engage in as a community, by means of which we accomplish or perform certain tasks or acts, and which function as the primordial metaphors for expressing the discernments and commitments that lie at the center of our common faith and life. This is not to say, of course, that symbols and rituals never become obsolete or that fresh ones can never be created. It is only to say that such alterations should be effected slowly and broadly, and that when they occur they will do so as a result of contours of communal needs, values and goals. Although it has come as a shock to many Roman Catholics, the reform instituted by the Second Vatican Council in the early 1960s with respect to the liturgy of the Mass strikes me as an excellent example of a It seeks a contextualist interpretation of the worship ritual. middle ground between past significance and contemporary life, without self-destructing into sheer subjectivism. Moreover, such reform establishes connections with other dimensions of the Christian community, thereby contributing to the unit y of the Church. Catholic and Protestant dialogue, as well as common worship and social action, are no longer simply a dream . Finally, theology itself must also be affected by a contextualist hermeneutic. The traditional model of theology as a metaph ysical counterpart to Newtonian science is clearly no longer viable. This includes all pontifical theologies, of both the philosophical and dogmatic varieties, left and right. Moreover, the individualized theologies of the existentialist and deconstructionist brands are of little help over the long and broad pull. The theologies most attentive to the contextualist motif would appear to be those being forged in the socio-political arena on the one hand and those working the "New Hermeneutic" field on the other hand. The former must be careful to allow for the distinction betwee n the mediating context and that which is being mediated, lest the truth of revelation be equated with the expedient. The latter must pay


Mediated Meaning: A Contextualist Approach to Henneneutical Method

39

increasing attention to developing the logic of language and story in a truly metaphoric mode, otherwise we shall once again be faced with a no-win choice between objectivism and subjectivism. To my mind, the theologian who is doing the most creative, yet substantive work in this mode is Sallie McFague.24 Drawing on the insights of the likes of Robert Funk and Dan Via, as well as insights of many of the thinkers already mentioned above, McFague explores the ramifications of approaching theology as an activity more akin to aesthetic criticism than to science or philosophy. Focusing on the role of parable as central both to Jesus's life and work and to the ongoing life of the Church, she stresses the "story" character of truth in general, as well as the metaphoric and mediational nature of revelation in particular. In McFague's words: The parables of the New Testament are united by a number of characteristics, of which one of the most outstanding is their concern with relationships of various kinds. What is important in the parables is not who the characters are (a static notion) but what they do (a dynamic one). The plot is always the heart of a parable, what a character or several characters decide in matters having to do with their relationships with each other. Whether one thinks of the parable of the Prodigal Son , the Good Samaritan, the Unjust Steward, or the Great Supper, it is relationships and decisions about them that are Just as the central Old Testament religious critical. language is relational--focused on the covenant between God and persons and their way of being in the world in community--likewise, if we look at Jesus as a parable of God, we have no alternative but to recognize personal, relational language as the most appropriate language about God. Whatever more one may wish to say about him, he was a person relating to other persons in loving service and transforming power.25 The cardinal concern for a contextual, mediational understanding of hermeneutics, in addition to its emphasis on those factors adumbrated in the foregoing pages, is the acknowledgement that whatever truth we possess, we carry in "earthen vessels." No truth can be revealed apart from the particulars of a concrete context, but no particular context can be equated with revealed truth. Mediated meaning must be shared both confidently and with humility, a rare and difficult combination, but a necessary one.


40

Gill

VI Permit me a brief "concluding unprofessional postscript." have no idea how my initial mentor, Professor Traina, will react to the foregoing reflections. On the one hand, my concern to allow the scripture to "speak for itself," liberated from the tyranny of traditional and/ or parochial agendae, is certainly traceable to his tireless and insightful efforts in the courses I took with him thirty years ago. On the other hand, he may complain that I have collapsed the distinction between interpretation, application and correlation. To this I can only answer that this distinction must be called into question, not in order to do away with it altogether, but in order to do justice to the manner and degree to which we are embodied and embedded in the language and thought patterns of our own heritage, both traditional and contemporary . Although there is no way we can extricate ourselves from these webs of meaning in order to be eyeball-toeyeball with truth and/ or reality, we can, by acknowledging both the limitations and the functional adequacy of our own knowledge claims, be confident without being arrogant in our hermeneutica l It is this circumspect confidence at which a endeavors. contextualist hermeneutic aims--and that toward which Robert Traina pointed his students by means of his own example.

Notes 1. A good overview is provided by Roy J. Howard in Three Faces of Hemieneutics (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1982).

2. Here see any "standard" text on interpretation within selected fields, such as literature, philosophy and theology. 3. Norman Perrin, Jesus and the Language of The Kingdom (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1980), p. 4. 4. W. Dilthey and Rudolph Bultmann represent this approach in a classic manner. See Dilthey's Selected Writings (London: Cambridge University Press, 1976) and Bultmann's Ke1ygma and Myth , ed. H. W. Bartsch (New York: Harper & Row, 1961). 5. Bultmann, Ke1ygma and Myth.


Mediated Meaning: A Contextualist Approach to Henneneutical Method

41

6. Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1976) and Writing and Difference (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978). 7. See Mead's On Social Psychology (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956). 8. Ibid., p. 4.

9. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (New York: Macmillan, 1953). 10. Ibid., pp. 120-122. 11 . See both Gadamer's T1Uth and Method (New York: Seabury Press, 1975) and Philosophical Henneneutics (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1976).

12. Gadamer, Philosophical Henneneutics, p. 62. 13. Especially significant is Austin's How to Do Things With Wonts (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1%1), pp. 132-163. 14. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, p. 70.

15. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception (New York: Humanities Press, 1962). 16. Ibid., Preface, p. xiii. 17. See Barfield's Poetic Diction (Middletown: Wesleyan University Press, 1973). 18. Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1%2). 19. See Pepper's World Hypotheses (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1942).

20. Here sec Mark Johnson and Thomas Lakoff, Metaphors We Live By (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980). 21. Nelson Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishers, 1978). 22. Ibid., p . 94.

23. See Hick's Faith and Knowledge (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1958), pp. 95-148. 24. See McFague's Speaking in Parables (1975), Metaphorical Theology (1982), and Models of God (1987), all published by Fortress Press. 25. McFague, Metaphorical Theology, p. 20.



Pirke 'Abot 1:2 (3) and the Synoptic Redactions of the Commands to Love God and Neighbor EUGENE E. LEMCIO I. INTRODUCTION Critical study of Jesus' teaching about love for God and neighbor (Matt 22:34-40, Mark 12:28- 34, Luke 10:25-28) always includes some attention to external evidence for both the form and content of the redaction. The point is commonly made that the twin commands had already been joined prior to the first century. 1 However, these extra-biblical data are not able to account for the synoptists' different renderings of Jesus' teaching; no r do the y explain how these two commands impinge upon Scripture, c ult and ethics. Consequentl y, it is the purpose of this article to arg ue that ' Abot 1:2 (3) and its subsequent transmiss ion in Judaism may help redaction critics to address these issues2 with greater precision. Our procedure will be to describe the phenomena within the redactional framework of each Gospel , introduce the pertinent "background" evidence, and then attempt to explain the relation between them. II. GOSPELS PHENOMENA

The Love Commandments In Matthew, Jesus is asked about " the great commandment in the law" (22:36). He responds with the deuteronomic injunction (6:5) to love God with all of one's faculties, calling this "the great and first co mmandment" (v 38). The command to love o ne's neighbor as oneself (Lev 19: 18) is "like" the first; and upon both

Eugene E. Lemcio Ph.D., is the professor of religion at Seattle Pacific University.

THE ASBURY THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

VOL. 43 No . l

1988


44

Lemcio

all the law and prophets "hang" (or may be derived from both , v 40).3 In Mark, the scribe's question is more universal in that he asks Jesus to identify the commandment which is "the first of all" (12:28). After citing the love commands, He declares quite absolutely that "There is no other commandment greater than these" (v 31). Unique to Mark, however, is the repetition of Jesus' response by the scribe (vv 32-33a) who then goes on to subordinate "all whole burnt offerings and sacrifices" to them (v 33b). When, according to Luke, a nomikos asks what he must do to inherit eternal !ife (I 0:25), Jesus directs him to find the answer in the Law. Jn reply, the expert cites the twin commands as " ... a single imperative ... without a connecting link as in Mark and Matthew."4 When Jesus urges him to find life by practic ing what he knows to be true (v 28), the irrepressible lawyer requests a definition for "neighbor" (v 29). There then follows the parable of the Good Samaritan, which disallows any boundar y- setting definition of neighborliness, since one must be prepared to sho w mercy even to an enemy in need (vv 30-37). Their R edactional S etting Each of these respective emphases regarding scriptural revelation, cult and behavior are in part, at least, expressions of each evangelist's redactional interests. That Matthew's lawyer should ask Jesus about the great commandment in the law (v 36) is not surpnsmg. Earlier, this concern to identify the heart of revealed religion appears in Matthew's formulation of the " G olden Rule" (7: 12) and in Jesus' accusing the religious leaders of neglecting the " ... weightier matters of the law: justice, mercy and faith" during their scrupulous efforts to tithe even herbs (23:2 3). Likewise, Jesus' response to the lawyer in terms of " law and prophets" (that is, the entire scriptural revelation) reflects the Matthean idio m in his report of Jesus' mission to fulfill " the la w and the prophets" (5: 17) rather than abolish them (cf. 7: 12). Intriguingly, in the latter instance as well as at 23:23 , these effo rts to identify the major thrust of Scripture occur within an affirmation of the need to observe the minor points, too (5: 18-1 9). Mark's concern to make these commands supersede the cultus fits with his redactional program also. He gives more attention to the debate about ritual cleanliness and dietary scrupulosity at 7: 123 (esp. v 19) than does Matthew ( 15: 1-20). His account of Jesus' attitude toward the Temple is also more harsh. Mark alone reports that , in His " cleaning" of the Temple , Jesus in effect closed it down by preventing the flow of traffic (11:16). Only Mark has Jesus citing Isa 56:3-7 to make the point that God had intended to make the shrine a place of prayer for all nations , not me re ly fo r


Pirke 'Abot 1:2 (3)

45

Jews (v 17). Finally, the Second Evangelist makes the false witnesses at the Sanhedrin's hearing attribute a more negative attitude of Jesus toward the shrine. There is no reference to its being the "Temple of God" (cf. Matthew 26:61 ). Whereas Jesus in Matthew only claims power to destroy it, in Mark He is alleged to have promised to destroy it and build one without human effort (14:58). Luke's stress upon merciful behavior (I 0:28, 37) corresponds to his rendering of "Q" material about love for one's enemies in 6:27-36. The Third Evangelist heightens the stress on "doing good" and concludes with the injunction to imitate God's mercy (rather than His perfection, as in Matt 5:43-48). Finally, one might suggest the following concerns which these modifications would have addressed. Matthew's subordination of the written revelation to these twin commands would have answered questions among his readers about the relation of Jesus' teaching to Jewish scripture and tradition. For Gentile Christians, confused by Jewish Christians who urged them to perfect their faith by dietary and cultic scrupulosity, Mark insisted that love for God and neighbor would keep them near to the Kingdom of God even if the cult were to be terminated by the Temple's destruction. Luke expanded " the neighborhood" to include such undesirables as the Samaritan. Although the stricken Jew's neighbors (the priest and the Levite) failed to show him mercy, the foreigner did. That Jews might mediate salvation to the Gentiles is radical enough; but to have the reverse occur, turns the world upside down. Such opportunities did occur in the early decades when Gentile churches came to the aid of the poor saints of Jerusalem (e.g. , I Cor 16:1-3). Thus, one can offer an account, based upon internal evidence, of the synoptic evangelists' renditions of Jesus' teaching about loving God and neighbor. Yet, it might be possible to understand them further in the light of certain " background" data. III. JUDAISM T estaments of the Twelve Patriarchs That Jesus was not the first to join the commands to love God and neighbor cannot be denied . They appear together in T. l ss. 5:2, 7:6 and T. Dan. 5:3.5 In no instance, however, are the y used to subordinate the Law and cultus; nor do they expand the boundaries of neighborliness in so radical a fashion.6 Consequently , the T estaments provide no means of accounting for the use which the Gospel writers make of the twin commands. Moreover, the usefulness of this material could be minimized by


46

Lemcio

any who would suspect Christian interpolations at this point. such cannot be claimed of the following data.

But

Pirke 'A bot 1:2 ( 3) A pronouncement attributed to one Simeon the Just stands at the head of Pirke 'Abot. Although Simeon's precise identity and date are still debated (ca. 350-200 B.c.E. ),7 the statement in question, authentic or not, clearly reflects an outlook possible only while the Second Temple stood:

Simeon the Just was of the survivors of the Great Assembly. He used to say, "on three things the World [or Age] stands: on the Torah, on the [Temple] service, and on deeds of lovingkindness." 9 This formulation by Simeon the Just is so all-embracing that Judah Goldin sees it as comprising the pillars " ... fundamental to the architecture of classical Judaism."10 Yet, they are even broader, for they deal with the fundamentals of religion. R. Herford put the matter precisely and succinctly: "The three things represent revelation, worship and sympathy, i.e., God's word to man, man's response to God, and man's love to his fellow men." 11 The impact of Simeon's statement was so profound that it dominated thinking for several centuries thereafter. Subsequent sages, while not directly helpful for our interpretation of the Gospels because of their late date, nevertheless show both how fundamental was the hold of Simeon's dictum (in that it was preserved intact) and how it became adapted to subsequent situations. Goldinl2 sees the earliest such adaptation in a tradition about R. Jochanan ben Zakkai which is preserved in 'Abot R. Nat 4. 13 Whether or not the account is early or authentic, a difference in mood with respect to 'Abot 1:2 (3) is evident in the request R. Jochanan allegedly made of Vespasian following the siege of Jerusalem. He asked only for Jabneh, that he might go " ... and teach [his] disciples and there establish a prayer (house) and perform all the commandments."14 For Goldin, this formulation represents an attempt to deal with the new situation by boldly reinterpreting the pillars of Simeon in the aftermath of


Pirke 'Abot 1:2 (3)

47

the War of 66-70 c.E. For the Torah, he made central the study and teaching of Torah; as a substitute for Temple worship (now impossible) came prayer, or acts like prayer; for deeds of piety, the Master prescribed acts of lovingkindness.15 In another tradition about R. Jochanan ben Zakkai, likewise preserved in 'Abot R. Nat. (4 in version A, 8 in B), the sage not only makes prayer a substitute for Temple service, he also subordinates it with the third element. On inspecting the ruined Temple, he comforted the distressed R . Joshua by maintaining (on the authority of Hos 6:6) that merciful deeds constitute an equally effective, alternative atonement. 16 The latter tack is continued by R . Nathan himself. After quoting each of Simeon's dicta (version A), he expounds the meaning of the pillars seriatim. Once again, Hos 6:6 provides the warrants for contending that both the study of Torah and the doing of merciful deeds are superior to burnt offerings. 17 Although Simeon's formulation was quoted verbatim through the third century,18 an even farther-reaching adaptation occurred in the wake of the disastrous wars of 132-135 c.E. In Pirke 'Abot l: 18 (19), in a formally parallel comment, this tradition is preserved: "Rabban Shimon ben Gamliel said: ' On three things the world stands: on Judgment, and on Truth and on Peace."'19 According to Jacob Neusner, such a statement " ... clearly represents a post-135 revision of no. 2: The Torah now is truth, a philosophizing tendency; the Temple service is now replaced by justice; and deeds of lovingkindness are replaced by peace."20 Thus was the legacy of Simeon the Just preserved and adapted after 70 c.E. Hos 6:6 played a prominent part in enabling the first and third of his "pillars" to subordinate the second when momentous historical events required equally decisive theological rethinking. Yet, the stream which we have followed had, if we interpret and appl y the data correctly, another tributary; namely, that of other Jews who differed with Simeon about the pillars of religion. And it is to them that we now turn. IV. 'A BOT AND THE GOSPELS In the Gospels, although Hos 6:6 is used to subordinate various cul tic practices (Matt 9: 12, 12:7), it is the conjunction of Deut 6:5 and Lev 19: 18 that subordinates all three of Simeon's pillars.21 H e had said that the world (or age to come) stands on the Torah. Jesus declared that both the Law and Prophets themselves "hang" on the twin commands to love God with one's entire being and neighbor as oneself (Matt 22:40). Simeon had maintained that the world stands on the Temple service. An unknown scribe


48

Lemcio

subordinated " ... all whole burnt offerings and sacrifices" to the love commands (Mark 12:33), an analysis which Jesus approved by pronouncing him "not far" from the Kingdom of God (v 34). Simeon had opined that the world or age to come stands on acts of lovingkindness. According to Luke, an anonymous lawyer eager to inherit eternal life (or life of the age [to come), Zoe aionios ) himself joined these love commands. In the parable of the Good Samaritan which follows, Jesus urged him to become a neighbor by performing deeds of mercy even to an enemy in need (10:2537). So, while for Simeon the foundations of existence now and hereafter were the written revelation, its cultic response, and merciful interpersonal behavior, the Evangelists portray Jesus and one guardian-interpreter of Jewish religion as maintaining pointfor-point that greater even than these is wholehearted, boundarytranscending love. In other words, my contention is that the Synoptic variants, seen against the backdrop of 'Abot 1:2 (3 ), portray debates among Jews wherein there is an effort to lay deeper or other foundations for ways of being religious that those which Simeon the Just had identified. This external evidence suggests that there was an earlier, or at least another, reason for the shape of these commandments than is usually offered. Both kinds of data may enable us to give a richer and fuller account of their significance. V. IMPLICATIONS

Redaction Although we argued above that the evangelists' versions of the love commands fit their overall redactional purposes, one must not suppose that they either reflect an exclusive concern or that they are essentially redactional in nature. There is, in fact, a great deal of overlap. Like Mark, Matthew is inclined to subordinate cultic and ceremonial matters to larger issues. So, he has Jesus invoke Hos 6:6 twice in order to criticize religious leaders for preferring ceremonial purity to showing mercy towards sinners (9: I 0-12) and for condemning innocents while maintaining cultic scrupulosity (12:1-7). Likewise, Matthew's and Mark's treatment of the encounter between Jesus and the rich man bears a striking resemblance to Luke's version of the commandments to love. In both instances, the quest is for (I) behavior (2) that will eventuate in eternal !ife (Matt 19:16, Mark 10:17, Luke 18:18. Cf. Luke 19:25). Both relate Jesus' directive (3) to behave mercifully (giving to the poor was regarded as a merciful act [Matt 19:21. Cf. 6:2-3 , Mark 10:21, Luke 18:22)). However, Matthew takes the matter another


Pirke 'Abot 1:2 (3)

49

step by appending (4) loving one's neighbor as oneself to the Decalogue (v 19. Cf. Luke 10:27). Finally, Matthew insists that the disposition towards one's enemy, of the kind exhibited by the Good Samaritan, mirrors the way in which God loves; and this enables one to fulfill the command to be teleios as He is (5:4348).22 Thus, the themes are transredactional ones.23 Furthermore, their commonality at this level runs deeper if one looks at the matter from the perspective of source and form criticism. The connections just cited span the triple tradition, Matthew and "L," and "Q" and "L." Moreover, they infuse logia, apophthegms (specifically, controversy dialogues) and parable.24 Therefore, both in content and form, the oral and written tradition portrays Jesus as one whose teaching dealt with the pillars of religion as these had been formulated by Simeon the Just and as they were being debated among religious experts of the day.25

History Having pursued these themes beyond their redactional level to the tradition which lay behind it, it now becomes necessary to press the matter still farther. Does the tradition reflect anything of the mind, if not the very words of Jesus? Perhaps the best entry into this complex matter lies via the extent of post-Easter Christology or soteriology at work.26 One thing seems immediately clear. The accounts have not undergone the sort of thoroughgoing Christianization that would have made Jesus the hero in each case. We recall the strong probability that the two commands had already been associated in one branch of Judaism a century and a half before. This is reflected in Luke, where it is the lawyer, not Jesus, who finds in the love commands the way to eternal life. Jesus simply urges him to act on what he has just discovered. Furthermore, in Mark, the sympathetic scribe, not Jesus, elevated agape over the cultus. Of course, in Matthew and Mark, Jesus does appear as the first to subordinate the Law (and prophets) to love for God and neighbor. But He emerges as the chief among several participants in a debate occurring among Jews and within Judaism . Perhaps more significantly, relation to Jesus' person is not made superior to obeying His teaching here as it is elsewhere in the Gospels. For example, in Matthew 19, the wealthy young man comes to Jesus for instruction about good behavior that will get him a hold on eternal life (v 16). Jesus answers that eschatological entry into life rests on keeping the commands, specifically the last five of the Decalogue , to which He adds Lev 19: 18, the command to love neighbor as self (vv 18-19). In response to the inquisi tor's


50

Lemcio

exemplary record of obedience in every respect, and to his sense of incompleteness (ti eti hystero, v 20), Jesus moves him on to perfection with the charge to give his earthly treasures to the poor in exchange for heavenly ones and to follow Him (v 21 ). None of this occurs in Matthew 22. Nor does it in Luke 10:25-27, in an analogous circumstance, where, as we saw, it is the interlocutor who supplies the answer to his own questions about inheriting eternal life . And Mark resists making Jesus (or allowing himself to) explain why the scribe, having answered so well in subordinating the cult to the love commands, is only near to the kingdom of God (10:33-34).27 Of course, a natural objection will be that such a construct requires a harmonistic gestalt for these three versions: either that Jesus addressed the issues of Scripture, cult and ethics on a single occasion (which the tradition or each evangelist related separatel y) or that He spoke to each issue at different moments throughout His career. I am not yet prepared to advocate either, no r can I, as an historian , rule out either option a priori. Only a more thoroughgoing study can say. Whatever the ultimate answers, it has perhaps become clearer that future analysis of the synoptic versions of Jesus' teaching about loving God and neighbor ought to consider the shape and significance of Pirke 'Abot 1:2 (3).

Notes 1. See the treatment of R. H. Fuller in a collection of essays by him, L. Schottroff, C. Burchard and M. J. Suggs: Essays on the Love Commandment (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1978), p. 47-52. More current is the study by Pheme Perkins, Love Commands in the New Testament (New York: Paulist, 1982), p. 12-21.

2. Although Strack and Billerbeck have cited 'Abot in connection with Matthew, their use of the statement more nearly fits the Markan version. H. L. Strack and P. Billerbeck, Das Evangelium mach Miitthaus erliiutert aus Talmund und Midrosclr (Munchen: Beck, 1956), p. 500. Vincent Taylor, referring to the passage for Mark, uses it in a way more appropriate to Matthew: The Gospel According to St. Marie, 2d ed. (New York: St. Martin's, 1966), p. 487, 489. No one, however, has used the saying to view the three synoptic versions "synoptically" and to account for them more fu!Jy thereby. Klaus Berger consults hellenistic and palestinian-Jewish sources in his massive study of these passages; nevertheless he does not cite Pirlce 'Abot. See Die Gesetzesauslegung Jesu, WMANT 40/1 (Neukirchen-Vluyn: Neukirchener Verlag, 1972), p. 56-257. 3. It is not necessary to the argument of this study to determine which of these


Pirke 'Abot 1:2 (3)

51

meanings is to be preferred. See R. H. Gundry for a treatment of the options: Mauhew: A CommentQI}' on his Literary and Theological An (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1982), p. 450. 4. Fuller, Essays, p. 44. 5. See Jub. 20:2-10 and T. Benj. 3:1-5 where both imperatives occur in the near context. In all of these, only one of the faculties appears: the whole or the true heart (T. /ss. 7:6, T. Dan 5:3). 6. Fuller, Essays, p. 48, is not correct to equate the generalization of T. Iss. 7:6 with the gospels' more far-reaching imperative to love one's enemy. 7. G. F. Moore, "Simeon the Righteous," in Jewish Studies in Memory of Israel Abrahams, ed. G. Kohut (New York: Jewish Institute of Religion, 1927), p. 348-364. 8. There is no variant discernable in the following texts and critical commentaries available to me: P. Blackman, Mishnayoth, 2d ed. (New York: Judaica Press, 1963), 4:490. R. Herford, Pirlce Aboth. The Ethics of the Talmud: Sayings of the Fathers (New York: Jewish Institute of Religion, 1945), p. 22. C. Taylor, Sayings of the Jewish Fathers, 2d ed. (Cambridge: The University Press, 1897-1900) p. 12-13. B. Viviano, Study as Worship: Aboth and the New Testament, SJLA 26 (Leiden: Brill, 1978), p. 708. 9. Of special significance for understanding the terminology of this passage is Judah Goldin's important study, "The Three Pillars of Simeon the Righteous," PMJR 27 (1958): 43-58. He makes a good case for the temporal-eschatological sense of hci5lm ("the Age" and even the "future") as well as the more spatial "world" of "universe." And he succeeds in arguing that the articular form hti5rl1 is more likely written Torah. The prevailing anarthrous and later usage refers to the wider-ranging tradition, both written and oral, which formed the mainstay of Jewish life and thought (p. 47-50). But he is less successful in making the case for rendering gmllot hsdfm as "acts of Piety" (in obedience to the written revelation) rather than "deeds of lovingkindness/ mercy," a meaning which he alleges is more appropriate to the situation of Jochanan be Zakkai and his successors and which kl msot expresses better (p. 43-47). However, while there is no denying that the sage and his "school" were exemplary exponents of merciful deeds, their legacy stemmed more directly from the Master's citation of Hos 6:6 than from Simeon's dictum. Acts of lovingkindness, he declared, would qualify as an alternative means of atonement, even though the Temple (the second of Simeon's pillars) had been destroyed in the war with Rome (see n. 16 below). Furthermore, Goldin's reference to R. Nathan's exposition of gmllot hsdiin is inappropriate on two counts: (1) the opinion of a later sage cannot, without further ado, define usage several centuries earlier, and (2) it is inconclusive-the example of Daniel includes both pious acts towards God and deeds of mercy/lovingkindness towards people. (See notes 13 and 17 below).

10. Ibid., p. 43. 11. R. Herford, "Pirke Aboth" APOT, ed. R. H. Charles (Oxford: the University Press, 1913) 2:691.


52

Lemcio

12. Goldin, "Pillars," p. 51. He takes proper notice of the variant expressions in Version B which do not, however, affect the point materially. 13. Subsequently, I shall refer to Goldin's translation of A in The Father.r According to Rabbi Nathan, Yale Judaica Series, vol. x, ed. J. Obermann (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1955). For version B of the same work (and title), I have consulted the translation and commentary by A. J. Saldarini, SJLA 11, ed. J . Neusner (Leiden: E. J . Brill, 1975). Each will hereafter be referred to in an abbreviated form: translator and page number. 14. Goldin, "Pillars," p. 51. 15. Ibid., but see n. 9 above, for the rendering of gmilot hsdim . 16. Goldin, The Fat!tm, p. 34 and Saldarini, p. 75. 17. Goldin, The Father.r, p. 32-35. Daniel exemplified such behavior in that " ... he used to outfit the bride and make her rejoice, accompany the dead, give a perutah to the poor, and pray three times a day... " {p. 35). It is otherwise in version B. None of the commentary on Torah and Temple service (found in chap. 5) corresponds to that in A. Furthermore, the exposition of "acts of lovingkindness" is postponed to chap. 8, where these deeds and words of Torah are both regarded (again by virtue of Hos 6:6) as superior to burnt offerings and sacrifices (Saldarini, p. 75). 18. J . Neusner, The Rabbinic Tradition About the Pharisees Before 70 (Leiden: Brill, 1971), 1:44. 19. Herford, Ethics, p. 38, whose translation this is, identifies him as the son of Gamliel I who appears to have died shortly before the siege of Jerusalem. Most, with Taylor, Sayings, p. 25, believe him to have been the son of Gamliel II and therefore put the date of his death near or just beyond the middle of the second century. Viviano, Study, p. 30-31, lists the texts which contain the order of the first two elements as they appear above and those in which they are reversed. This detail does not detract from the observation that a substantial revision has occurred. 20. Neusncr, Rabbinic Traditions, 1:18. 21. Dcut 11:13, which echoes 6:5, is quoted by R. Nathan in connection with the discussion of Temple service (only in version A, Goldin, The Father.r , p. 33) but not in an effort to subordinate it. 22. Mark and Luke exhibit fewer such inter-Gospel connections. Both, however, heighten the ultimate significance of the twin commands more that Matthew. In commending the scribe's subordination of the cult by them, Jesus concludes the scene with the assurance, "You arc not far from the kingdom of God" (v 34). Th is comment is the near equivalent of Jesus' teaching that the doing of these commands will enable one to inherit eternal life (Luke 10:25, 28, 37). Luke's attitude towards the cult is more difficult to assess at this point. He may have lodged an implied criticism of it in the parable of the Good Samaritan, who became neighbor to the


Pirke 'Abot 1:2 (3)

53

stricken Jew whom both a priest and Levite bypassed in order to avoid ritual defilement. 23. Ordinarily, redaction cnt1cism says that the Gospel writers are ultimately responsible for the shape of traditions in their works. True enough; but this could come about by allowance of compatible things to stand as much as by adaptation . And the latter could include the exaggeration of what is traditionally and even historically the case. For example, even though Mark (more that other gospel writers) describes Jesus as a didaskalos, we cannot deny that Jesus was, in fact, a teacher. I have argued this and similar points more fully elsewhere: "External Evidence for the Structure and Function of Mark" 4:1-20, 7:14-23 and 8:14-21," ITS 29/2 (1978): 323-338, esp. pp. 331-338. 24. For convenience, I have simply used the categories popularized by Rudolf Bultmann. While nomenclature may be debatable, the larger point is that numerous forms are impressed with similar teaching. See The History of the Synoptic Tradition, trans. John Marsh, 2d ed. (New York: Harper & Row, 1968), pp. 16, 49, 51, 79, 178. 25. Such a phenomenon is routinely recognized regarding Jesus' teaching on divorce. Matthew's version (19:9) reflects the more liberal position of Shammai, while the other synoptists' correspond to that of the stricter Hillel (Mark 10:10/ Luke 16:17). See Gundry, Matthew, p. 377, where m . Git. 9:10 is cited. 26. I have applied thjs method of getting at the issue more fully in "The Parables of the Great Supper and the Wedding Feast: History, Redaction and Canon," HBT 8/1 (June 1986): 1-26, esp. pp. 7-11, 13-17. 27. Fuller, Essays, p. 47, lends his support to those who claim that " ...the preference of the moral law over the sacrificial cult presupposes a Hellenistic-Jewish rather than rabbinic understanding of the law." A similar point is made by Perkins, Love Commands, p. 23. However, this view ignores the fact that such a "preference" is as Hebraic as Hos 6:6 and as rabbinic as Jochanan b. Zakkai and R. Nathan.



Some Observations On The New Testament Concept of "Witness" DONALD G. MILLER I

"Witness" is a significant New Testament word. M artus occurs thirty-four times; the verb form martureo appears seventy-nine times; the nouns marturia and marturion total fifty-seven uses between them. The concept appears sparingly in the Synoptic Gospels, but is concentrated in the Johannine literature and the Acts of the Apostles. This distribution of its usage suggests that it is a vital aspect of the Church's growth from a local Jerusalem group to a world-wide movement, and contributed much to the propagation of the belief that "Jesus is the Christ, the Son of God" through which believers found " life in His name" (John 20:21 ). Its importance, however, goes beyond statistical considerations. Its importance lies in its meaning, and in its close affinity to the nature of the Christian faith as a historic religion. The Christian faith dawned on the world as a "light shin[ing] in the darkness" of paganism (John 11:5a; see Eph 6:12), with a power that "delivered [them] from the dominion of darkness" (Col 1:13a). It came into a world filled with "many 'gods' and many 'lords"' (1 Cor 8:5b)-those of Mt. Olympus and the temples of Rome, and the deities of the mystery religions from Egypt such as Isis and Osiris; and many philosophies--such as Epicureanism and Stoicism which commanded the loyalties of many for whom the ancient gods had died. It confronted all this with a simple account of a man named Jesus in whom, it was claimed, the one, living eternal God had visited the earth. Here was something new, something different. The home of

Dr. Donald G. Miller has degrees fonn Greenville College, The Biblical Seminary in New York and New York University. He has served on the fa culties of The Biblical Seminary in New York, Union Theological Seminary in Virginia, Lutheran Theological Seminary in Gettysburg, Pennsylvania and as president of Pittsburgh Theological Seminary.

THE ASBURY THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

VOL 43 No. l

1988


56

Miller

the Olympian gods was "shut from the sight of men on earth by clouds."' No one ever shook hands with Zeus. No one ever had lunch with Jupiter. No one ever rode out a storm in a little boat with Isis or Osiris. Those deities never wore sandals. Their feet never touched the earth; they were never soiled by the dust of the road we walk. But here was a god " who for a little while was made lower than the angels," who "share[d] in flesh and blood ," who was "made like His brethren in every respect" (Heb 2:9a, I 4a, I 7a). This was not mythology, but history; not fairy tale, but fact. This was no god " shut from the sight of men by clouds," but who was born in the animal stall of an overcrowded inn in a little village locatable on a map; who was accessible to both the humble and the great; who was a refugee in Egypt; who lived and taught on the soil of a Roman province; who had identifiable disciples, visited identifiable places, ran into trouble with the law under an identifiable Roman procurator; who was condemned to death, executed and buried by identifiable friends; and appeared alive to so me of them following His death and burial. What is more, this was not an historically isolated phenomenon , appearing out of the blue without background or preparat ion. It was vitall y related to a unique series of historic events wh ich lay behind it. It was a culmination of two thousand years of Jewish history. While other religions were speculating abo ut the doings in "the remote heavenly palaces of the gods,"2 the Jews had been observing Yahweh at work in history. As a colleag ue of mine once remarked , "you never get much heresy where the Old Testament is central, because it never allows yo u to get away from history." 3 You cannot escape histo ry in the Old Testament because it is the record of a historic people and their experiences on this planet. It has to do with the Pharaohs of Egypt; with Sennacherib, Sargon and Shalmaneser of Assyria; with Nebuchadnezzer of C haldea; and Cyrus of Persia. It records the doings of the ki ngs of Israel and Judah, the activities of living prophets, the record of whose doings abide until the present. So it is natural that the Christian faith should keep its roots deeply in history and not allow itself to get airborne into gnostic speculations . It is essentially a story of the God who had made himself known to the " fathers by the prophe ts," now speaki ng His full and final word "by a Son" (Heb I: I, 2). Christianity is basically the story of this Son. As Dr. George Arthur Buttrick once said: " In a sense, yo u can state the Christian faith in six words: 'The most wonderful thing has happened."' 4 He re is where "witness" in its primary sense became essential. The story must be told by those who had "witnessed" it. The elemental meaning of martus is a legal one, where so meone who


Some Obsuvations On The New Testament Concept of 'Witness"

57

has observed an event, or heard words spoken, or seen the signing of a deed , appears in court to authenticate such. To witness, therefore, is to rehearse what one has seen or heard , to verify the factuality of something.s It was for this reason that the Gospels were written and ultimately selected by the Church as bearing essentiall y the "witness" of the apostles, who were described by Luke as " eyewitnesses" of the things narrated . The importance of this apostolic "testimony" to what had happened was stressed by the apostles themselves when, in selecting one to take the place of the defected Judas "as a witness to [Jesus'] Resurrection," they insisted that he must be "one of the men who have accompanied us during all the time that the Lord Jesus went in and out among us, beginning from the baptism of John until the day when He was taken up ..." (Acts 1:21 ). The facts about Jesus were not m ythological but rather "a narrative [an historic account] of the things [the events] which have been accomplished [happened, taken place] among us, just as the y were delivered [handed down] to us by those who from the beginning were eyewitnesses ..." (Luke I: I, 2). The "witness" was not just to the Resurrection , but to the whole story of things that had happened on Palestinian soil in ongoing historic events, to real people. These "witnesses" were identifiable human beings, who toiled and sweated over heavy water-soaked fishing nets, who both collected and paid taxes, who bartered in market-places, some of whom were " dagger men" who sought opportunity to dispatch hated Romans or Jewish collaborators to the other world--all of whom had behind them the two -thousand-year history of a nation struggling agai nst great odds for survival in a hostile world, and were not accustomed to living on mythical imaginings nor hallucinatory visions. The necessity of the historic witness of the apostles to the events which had produced the Christian Church was effectively illustrated many years ago by Professor H. H. Farmer of Cambridge University. He contrasted Christianity as a historic religion with a nonhistoric religion such as Hinduism: It is theoreticall y conceivable that all the sacred books of Hinduism, and every Hindu, might be utterly destroyed , and yet substantially the same religion reappear. .. .Indeed it would fit harmoniously into the Hindu scheme of thought to suppose that if Hinduism vanished today it would reappear tomorrow, fifty years, a thousand years hence. But were all Christian records and all Christians extirpated, Christianity could not recur again . In its occurrence ... without a witness, it would flatly contradict all that it had To put it paradoxically, in always claimed to be.


58

Miller happening again it would show that it had never, according to its own definition of itself, happened at all.6

Christianity rests on a story of events. If nobody knew the events, nobody could be a Christian. For this reason, each generation must return to the Scriptures. The Bible will always remain central to the Church's witness, for it contains the story which brought the Church into being and will continue to nourish it to the end. The difference between the apostolic generation and all subsequent generations is that they could speak of that "which we have heard, which we have seen with our eyes, which we have looked upon and touched with our hands" (I John 1: I), whereas the others must repeat a story at which they themselves were not present. The Fourth Gospel points the dividing line between those who, like Thomas, had believed because they had "seen" and "those who have not seen and yet believe" (John 20:29). II

But the apostles "witness" in yet another sense of the word. Strathmann has pointed out that both in classical Greek and in the Septuagint, martus and its cognates are frequently used in the secondary sense of attestation of truth rather than mere f act .7 The "witness" interprets the hidden meaning of observable realities. The second Isaiah speaks of Israel as a "witness" to "the people who are blind, yet have eyes, who are deaf, yet have ears" (43:8). Because Israel knows and believes and understands that " before [Yahweh] no god was formed, nor shall there be any after" Him , they are to "witness" this to those who know it not. They are to interpret to others the meaning of God's action with them . Events do not always carry their significance in themselves. They must be interpreted. For example, had one, ignorant of baseball, been taken to Forbes Field in Pittsburgh in the Fall of 1960 to see the last game of the World Series, he would have seen men, in batting practice before the game, hitting with a wooden club a small white sphere which occasionally went over the fence. This would have been just an illustration of the mechanical force of propulsion over gravity. When, however, in the last of the ninth inning, with two outs and the Pittsburgh Pirates behind , a little chap named Mazeroski, whose propulsive habits were at best questionable, propelled the little sphere over the fence , the uninitiated onlooker would not have understood why the crowd responded with fits of near insanity. One would have had to interpret the event to him to give it any meaning. The incident ended the game with a sudden, unexpected reversal of the winning side; it installed the Pirates as world champions; it added a fat


Some Observations On The New Testament Concept of "Witness"

59

paycheck to the yearly earnings of the hitter and his teammates, and by that much reduced the paychecks of their Yankee opponents; it put Pittsburgh on the sports map and caused every sports writer in the world to write about it; and it gave habitual drunkards a better reason for getting drunk than they had had for some time. To understand the significance of an event, it is necessary to set it in a context of meaning . The necessity of this in the realm of faith may be seen in the case of the Ethiopian eunuch who was reading the scroll of the prophet Isaiah as his chariot carried him home from a pilgrimage to Jerusalem. "Do you understand what you are reading?" asked Philip. "How can I," he replied , "unless some one guides [explains, teaches) me?" Then we are told, "Philip opened his mouth, and beginning with this scripture he told him the good The story of Jesus must be news of Jesus" (Acts 8:30ff). interpreted. It could be just a story of a starry-eyed young Jewis h man who fell afoul of the authorities in a good cause and found what many reformers have found, that it doesn't pay to stick one's neck out too far. Or, it could be the story of the coming of the eternal God in a unique, decisive incursion into human history, to redeem the world from its thralldom to evil. The event itself must be understood in its context of meaning. The facts themselves are not enough. A recent British writer has fulminated against Edward Gibbon as a "pseudo-historian." Of him the writer says: Accurate in every statement of his work, there has lived no individual writer responsible for a greater volume of inferential falsehood .... Following his method, there might be compiled with equal regard for fact and disdain of the truth, a chronicle of the American continent from the sexual shortcomings of transatlantic presidents, fortified by an implicit belief in the veracity of the Hearst press.s In order to avoid "inferential falsehood," with a high "regard for fact" but a "disdain of the truth," the Church set up the canon of the Scriptures as the authoritative guide to all future developing tradition . In so doing, it did not impart any authority to the Scriptures- -it merely recognized the innate apostolic authority of the interpretation of the sacred events contained therein, by which it had been brought into being and under which its subsequently developing tradition was to be controlled.9 Those in the apostolic generation , therefore, were the indispensable and decisive "witnesses" both to the fact s which underlie our faith and to the m eaning of those facts for faith.


60

Miller III

But the "witness" did not stop with that generation. There is a broader sense in which all Christians are " witnesses." They "echo" the original witness of the apostles by rehearsing the facts they recounted and by reiterating the apostolic interpretation of those facts. Timothy, for example, was a non-Palestinian Greek who never knew Jesus in the Flesh, but Paul counseled him, "Do not be ashamed then of testifying to our Lord" (2 Tim I:8a). He was obviously free, in his testifying, to go beyond mere catechetical repetition of apostolic teaching, but in using his own words he was to follow "the pattern of the sound words" which he had heard from Paul and to "guard the truth" which had been entrusted to him by the Holy Spirit who dwelt within him (2 Tim I: I 3f). He was not to create new truth, but to rehearse truth which had been entrusted to him by Paul and others. Even Paul, although he was a direct witness to the Resurrection by having been granted a post-Resurrection appearance of Jesus (Acts 22:6f; 26: I 2ff; Gal I: I Sf; I Cor 9: l, 15:8), was dependent on the "witness" of the other apostles as to the historic facts of our Lord's earthly life. When he described the Lord's Supper, he could only pass on the tradition he had "received." He speaks of receiving it "from the Lord," but the entire passage suggests that he does not mean that it had been divinely revealed to him, but had come to him through a tradition at the beginning of which stands the historical Jesus.10 So the entire Christian community is engaged in "witness" as the tradition is received and passed on from generation to generation. As a guide to the content of what that witness should be, it is instructive to examine the New Testament descriptions of the apostolic witness . To what, or to whom, were they witnessing ? What was the content of their testimony? As we have seen , their central and unique attestation can be made by subsequent generations only in a secondary sense- -by rehearsing their primary witness to the Resurrection of Jesus. In Peter's sermon to Cornelius, he affirmed that "God raised (Jesus] on the third day and made Him manifest, not to all the people but to us who were chosen by God as witnesses ..." (Acts 10:40a; italics mine). Paul confirms the uniqueness of the apostolic witness to the Resurrection when, in listing the series of post-Resurrection appearances, he lists the appearance to him as "last of all" ( I Cor I 5:8a); that is, the last in a series after which there are to be no more . No emotional experiences, or alleged appearances of the risen Christ to sub-apostolic people, therefore, are to be c redited as genuine post-Resurrection appearances commensurate with what happened to those "who were chosen by God as witnesses" to the


Some Observations On The New Testament Concept of ''Witness"

61

Resurrection. We must depend on the apostolic "witness" at this point; not subsequent occult experiences. When, therefore, we hear of experiences such as that of the late Bishop Pike, who apparently having reservations about the apostolic testimony to the Resurrection, wanted us to believe in the life beyond because of certain occult communications he had with his deceased son, we cannot incorporate such experiences into the tradition of genuine Christian testimony. They are alien to normative Christianity. At this point the apostolic "witness" is final. We are driven back on it--or nothing. Subsequent generations can only recapitulate their testimony. But in echoing the apostolic testimony to Jesus' Resurrection, the re-presentation of succeeding generations must include the context in which that testimony was made. Granted the fact of the Resurrection witnessed solely by the apostles, subsequent generations must present along with it the accompany ing apostolic train of thoug ht. They can, for example, follow Paul in testifying to the consequences of failing to believe that Christ has been raised; to the significance of Christ's Resurrection as "first fruits" of the hope of our own resurrection as His final triumph over death; and to the nature of the mystery involved in the "spiritual body" which Paul contrasts with the "physical body" we now possess (see I Cor 15: l 2f). A part of the apostolic "witness" in which subsequent generations may share, too, is found in the Lukan setting where the witness to the Resurrection is related to its background in the Old T estament Scriptures , with the Suffering Servant as the key to understanding the preparation for the event, and the consequent implication " that repentance and forgiveness of sins should be preached in His name to all nations" (Luke 24:26f, 44ff). Guidance is found also in Peter's word to Cornelius when he insisted that the apostles were commissioned not only to "witness" to "all that He did both in the country of the Jews and in Jerusalem," and to His "death by hanging ... on a tree," and to the fact that "God raised Him on the third day," but also "to testify that He is the one ordained by God to be the judge of the living and the dead" because "all the prophets bear witness that every one who believes in Him receives forgiveness of sins through His name" (Acts 10:39ff). This is all part of the apostolic "witness" which all subsequent generations must re-present till "the last syllable of recorded time." But note that this "witness" is always focused on Jesus and what God has accomplished through him, not on subjective "experience" as an outcome of believing this. Their "experience" never became their "gospel." As Paul said, "what we preach is not ourselves, but Jesus Christ as Lord ..." (2 Cor 4:5a). Paul


62

Miller

rehearsed his experience with the risen Christ on the road to Damascus in Acts 22 and 26 in testifying to the fact that Christ was alive, in establishing his commission to "be a witness for Him to all men" of what he had "seen and heard" (22:15b, 26:16b), and in insisting on his status as an apostle (Gal 1:11-2:10); but the normal focus of his evangelistic witnessing was not on his own experience but on the death and Resurrection of Jesus as the fulfillment of the prophetic message of the Old Testament. Paul's first recorded sermon in the synagogue at Antioch was not a description of his conversion, nor a word about his own inner spiritual life. It was a rehearsal of Jewish history from the Exodus, through David , to John the Baptist; an affirmation " that what God promised to the fathers, this He has fulfilled to us their children by raising Jesus"; and the conclusion that "every one that believes is freed from everything from which you could not be freed by the law of Moses" through the "forgiveness of sins" (Acts l3:16ff). In his defense before Agrippa, Paul describes his ministry as "testifying both to small and great, saying nothing but what the prophets and Moses said would come to pass: that the Christ must suffer, and that, by being the first to rise from the dead, He would proclaim light both to the people [the Jews] and to the Gentiles" (Acts 26:22f). Paul also counseled Timothy: "Do not be ashamed then of testifying to our Lord ... who abolished death and brought life and immortality to light through the Gospel" (2 Tim 1:5a, l Ob). Timothy was not urged to share with his hearers the latest state of his religious emotions, nor the content of some spiritual vision he had recently had , nor his own ideas about God, nor some alleged word spoken to him b y God during his morning devotions, but to affirm that God in Christ had destroyed man's last enemy--death, and that because of that we may be "more than conquerors through Him who loved us," from whose love nothing "in all creation can separate us" (Rom 8:37ff). As Eugene H. Peterson has aptly stated: "When we witness we do not unpack the contents of our own emotional suitcases for the titillation of voyeurs, we point to what God has revealed." 11 Many who follow the "experience-centered" method of Christian witness by continually relating their own experiences of grace, claim John Wesley as their mentor. I am wondering how correct they are. Although I am not an expert on Wesle y, I have read rather widely in his writings, and do not recall one single reference to his "Aldersgate" experience save the one description of it in his Journal. It did not seem to become his "gospel." And when, in many other passages in his Journal, he relates so me remarkable instance of providence in preserving him from harm


Some Observations On The New Testament Concept of "Witness"

63

on his countless journeys to preach, there is no evidence that these experiences were recounted in his sermons, or used as evangelistic tools. It has been said of his sermons that one could develop a good systematic theology from them , because they are directed to an exposition of the faith rather than rehearsals of his experience of the faith. P. T. Forsyth made a distinction between "the experience ... of redemption" and "the experience of a redeemer. Because it is not the sense of the experience that is the main matter, but the s ource of the experience, and its content. It is not our experience we are conscious of--that would be self-conscious piety--but it is Christ. It is not our experience we preach , but the Christ who comes in our experience." 12 One of the rarest and most treasured graces possible in Christian experience is genuine humility. The humblest man I ever knew would have been surprised if one had asked him how he became humble. He would probably have answered that he had never thought of himself as humble. It was his experience of Christ that made him humble, not his experience of humility. And what made him humble was that he was so obsessed with Christ, and service to him, that it never occurred to him to analyze his own experience, or talk of it. He could not have written the bestseller I once heard of, entitled Humility and How I Attained It! On the other hand, I think that perhaps the proudest man I ever saw was one who argued that God never asks anything of us that we are unable to attain. If asked whether he really, at all times without exception, kept the second great commandment, "Thou shalt love thy love thy neighbor as thyself," he likely would have answered "Yes!" I once heard Professor Eduard Schweizer, of Zurich, illustrate in a lecture the difference between the objective and the subjective quality of human experience. He said: "I ask you, 'What happened at the theater last Friday evening?' If you should reply, 'Oh, it was wonderful! I was deeply moved! Chills went up and down my spine, my eyes were filled with tears; I have never experienced such an exalted mood before in my whole life!' I should have to reply, 'But you haven't answered my question. I did not ask what happened to you, but what happened at the theater?'" If what happened there could produce such a marked response, testimony to the response might indeed encourage the hearer to go the play to find out for himself, but it would be the play it self and not someone else's experience of the play which would be crucial. A ware of this, when William Carey was visited on his deathbed by his younger colleague, Alexander Duff, and Duff recounted the many contributions Carey had made to India through his life, Carey replied: "Mr Duff, ... when I am gone say


64

Miller

nothing about Dr. Carey--speak about Dr. Carey's Saviour." 13 This has two important concomitants. First, if one rest o ne's faith on experience rather than the source of his experience, it is difficult to know whose experience should be normative. On a visit to the Mormon Tabernacle a few years ago, I picked up a tract written by a female deep sea diver, accompanied by a very enticing photograph. It was her testimony. She had been taking instruction in the Mormon faith for some months when suddenl y, in a deep dive many feet below the surface of the water, the truth of the Mormon persuasion was clearly revealed to her and she experienced the meaning of life through that revelation in a way that solved all her problems and made her a radia nt and triumphant believer. If one rests one's case on experience, wh y is not her experience as valid as anyone else's? And most certainly, the Christian Science appeal rests quite solidly on Mrs. Edd y's testimony to her "healing" and on that of subsequent followers . If the retelling of religious experiences is the best me thod of propagating religious faith, then it would seem that those approached would be in the position of consumers influenced by advertising who are left to pick and choose that which is most appealing. On the other hand, to present the proposal of Jesus alongside others, to examine carefully the long history leading up to Him in the old Testament, to expose one's self to the appeal of His character, claims and teachings in the light of the character , claims and teachings of others, along with the apostolic testimo ny to His death and Resurrection (which involve truths claimed for no other religious leader), furnishes a more solid basis for belief than the states of feelings or the religious experiences claimed by His followers. The ultimate question for faith must be: Is He trustworthy? Conceivably, under the influence of drugs one could have a feeling of emotional euphoria while drowning. On the other hand, a young man might experience all the normal emotional terror of drowning until he was unconscious, yet be saved by a strong swimmer who rescues him, pumps the water out of his lungs, and restores him to wholeness. The issue in a drowning crisis is not how does one feel, but what is the capability of the rescuer? Luther wrote to one in this ve in when, eschewing all supports from experience, he rested his hope fully on the adequacy of Christ. And I, my loving Brentius ...do use to think in this manner, namely, as if in my heart were no quality or virtue at all which is called faith or love, but I set all on Christ , and say, my formalis justitia, that is, my sure, my constan t and complete righteousness, in which there is no want or


Some Observations On The New Testament Concept of "Witness"

65

failing, but is as before God it ought to be, is Christ my Lord and Savior.14 Second, Dora Greenwell, in a classic devotional book, The Patience of Hope, written over a century and a quarter ago, raised the issue of the spiritual uncertainty of a faith which rests on subjective experience rather than on Him who is the source of that experience. If faith rests on experience, then that faith is shaky when the experience cools, and thus one's confidence is put at the mercy of one's changing emotional states, or subjected to the functioning of the liver or endocrine glands. Greenwell wrote: Certain systems lay a pressure upon the subjective side greater than the spirit of man is at all times able to bear; working out all things from the depths of individual consciousness, as if truth were not there at all until they are (manifestly) there for us. She gently chided Wesley, who though he laudably "felt and preached Christ both freely and fully," yet by giving "central importance ... to conscious spiritual work in men" tended, in some degree, "to withdraw the soul's eye from Christ, to fix it upon what is going on within itself."15 This criticism was based on Wesley's early views, expressed frequently but especially clearly in a letter in which he says that he insists "in all my writings, and in all my preaching" on a subjective assurance, a "perceptible inspiration," of one's standing with Christ. We mean that inspiration of God's Holy Spirit, whereby He fills us with righteousness, peace, and joy, with love to Him and all mankind. And we believe it cannot be, in the nature of things, that a man should be filled with this ... without perceiving it as clearly as he does the light of the sun. 16 Although, as we have seen, Wesley did not use Christian experience as the basis of faith, it is clear from these and other statements that he used it as evidence of the reality of one's faith. If one were not subjectively assured of one's saving relation to Christ, it was doubtful whether he or she had such a relationship. The evidence for faith that one is reconciled to God does not then rest ultimately on what Christ has done, but on one's "perceiving ... as clearly as he does the light of the sun" that he is filled with "righteousness, peace, and joy" and with "love to


66

Miller

[God] and all mankind." Dora Greenwell apparently did not know, nor do a good many followers of Wesley, that in later years he seemed to recant this stern insistence on a subjective assurance. On March 28, 1768, when Wesley was sixty-five years of age, he wrote to Thomas Rutherforth, Regius Professor of Divinity at Cambridge University: I believe a consciousness of being in ... favour ... is the common privilege of Christians fearing God and working righteousness. Yet I do not affirm there are no exceptions to this general rule. Possibly some may be in the favour of God, and yet go mourning all the day long. But I believe this is usually owing either to disorder of body or

ignorance of gospel promises. Therefore I have not for many years thought a consciousness of acceptance to be essential to justifying faith. 17 On March 9, 1782, when Wesley was seventy-nine years of age, he wrote to Ann Loxdale, who was having difficulty with her Christian experience, complaining "But I am not increasing in the divine life": That is your mistake . Perhaps you are now increasing therein faster than ever you did since you were justified. It is true that the usual method of our Lord is to purify us by joy in the Holy Ghost and a full consciousness of His love. But I have known several exempt cases, and I am clearly satisfied yours is one ....1s But even more startling is Wesley's confession to his brother, Charles, when he was sixty-three years of age: And yet this is the mystery, I do not love God. I never did. Therefore I never believed in the Christian sense of the word. Therefore I am only an honest heathen, a proselyte of the Temple, one of the phoboumenoi ton theon ... .I have no direct witness, I do not say that I am a child of God .... 19 Able interpreters of Wesley have attributed this strange statement to Wesley's physical condition at the time it was made, brought on by overwork and strain.20 To the extent that such an interpretation is valid, it would seem to confirm the fact that to


Some Observations On The New Testament Concept of "Witness"

67

the degree that one's confidence of acceptance with God rests on subjective experience, to that degree one is put at the mercy of his or her physical makeup. Wesley was a sufficiently great man to change his mind when convinced that he had been mistaken. Apparently, in his maturity, through further study of the Scriptures and a deeper understanding of the ups and downs of the struggle of faith, he discovered , with Luther, that faith rests solely on Christ, and that one may be held by Christ even when his own awareness of that is dim. I believe he would finally have agreed with Dora Greenwell: Happy for us, if Christ can look [at us) and find His own image reflected, however faintly; but we must look at Him, at the sun in the heavens, not at the sun in the brook, its broken and ever-varying reflection. So long as we are resting in anything within ourselves, be it even in a work of grace, there remains, at least to honest hearts, a ground for continual restlessness and continual disappointment. To know that we have nothing, are nothing, out of Christ, is to know the truth which makes us free. 21 In this vein, P.T. Forsyth says: In your faith you are more conscious and sure of Him than you are of your faith. For your faith, you well know, may fail Him, but you know still better that He will not fail your faith. And you are more conscious and sure of Him, as the source and cause of your experience, than you are of the experience itself, which you forget to think of. The very apostles never asked us to believe their experience, nor to believe on the ground of it, but to believe with them in Christ. 22 IV There is one further aspect of "witness" in the New Testament that should not be overlooked. It is the nonverbal testimony of the Christian community manifested by their commitment to the truths they profess. The facts on which faith is based, and the unique interpretation of the meaning of those facts which faith gives, is embodied in a life lived in commitment to those facts and the truths they imply. This does not mean that these facts and their meaning are irrelevant if not adequately embodied in a committed community. If that were so, Christian truth would have vanished long ago in the light of the failure of both Israel and the Church to embody their faith. The very judgment of God


68

Miller

brought on by the lapses, however, is itself a witness that they should not have occurred, and God's faithfulness both to Israel and the Church is witness to the truth they often fail to embody. This is clear in the Old Testament where Israel's survival of the judgment of the Exile becomes a "witness" to the nations of the God by whom they survived. Israel's very existence after the Exile made them "witnesses" to Yahweh's saving purpose and His lordship of history (Isa 53:9ff). So the very existence of the Christian community, in spite of its lapses and failures and weaknesses and denials, bears witness to the God to whom it is committed and testifies to the fact that the truth by which it li ves is greater than it is. The Church is summoned to live by the faith which it professes, and to the extent that its failure to do so is willful and blatant, it is under the judgment of God . But the God to whom the Church witnesses is greater than it is, and will not " leave himself without witness" even when the Church fails Him . Years ago I heard Dr. George W. Richards tell of E. Stanley Jones asking Gandhi what he would like him to tell the American Christians when he visited America. Gandhi replied: "Tell them to live their religion ." Dr. Richards remarked that this indicated Gandhi's failure to understand the Christian faith. This was a modern repetition of the old Pharisaic notion that if all Israelites would only keep the law for twenty-four hours, Messiah would come . This would place the achievement of God's purpose in the hands of men rather than in the will of God . It manifests, too, a faulty estimate of the tragedy of the human situation, ass um ing that by human effort, even on the part of good and devout people, the kingdom of God can be established on the earth and the ravages of the human condition be overcome. Karl Bart h frequently quoted the phrase: Die providentia et hominum confusione. The providence of God and the confusion, or bungling , of people--even good people--accounts for history. T he purpose of God for humankind is too great ever to be perfectly embodied in history, either in the life of individuals or the structures of society. Utopians, both secular or sacred , hold out false hopes. There will never be a time when we shall not have to continue praying, "Thy kingdom come," so long as history lasts. The kingdom will come as God's gift in His own way and time. Committed persons do not achieve it, but bear witness to its co:ning because God is God, and they seek to live now--though failing at every turn--in a way that will be commensurate with that kingdom when it comes. Browning's familiar saying, "A man's reach should exceed his grasp, or what's a heaven for?" puts it well . But a genuinely believing person keeps reaching and, aware with Paul that he or


Some Observations On The New Testament Concept of "Witness"

69

she is not "already at the goal," presses on "toward the goal for the prize of the upward call of God in Christ Jesus {Phil 3: 13 ). And even an imperfect effort to live one's faith, to the degree that a person is genuinely penitent, is a silent witness to that truth which is greater than human achievement. Discerning people can distinguish between a willful flaunting of the Christian ideal--the fraudulent attitude that says, "let us sin that grace may abound"-and the authentic failure of a high-minded struggler after righteousness. The life-commitment of a believer to the truth he or she attests, and the effort in the long history of the Church to read the meaning of the judgments of God upon it and to renew its life accordingly, are eloquent "witness" to the fact that God is at work in the world through His Church and that He speaks to "those who have ears to hear." John Calvin once suggested that in the liturgy of the Church the Gloria in excelsis be replaced by a recital of the Ten Commandments, thus witnessing that confessing a true desire to live by them would be the best way to glorify God. The supreme commitment of life to the glory of God is a mighty witness to Him.

v This leads to the ultimate in "witness"--the laying down of one's life for God's glory. The New Testament applies the word "witness" to Jesus in the laying down of His life {I Tim 6: 13), and twice in the Revelation applies it to those who had died martyrs' deaths (2: 13, 17:6). This usage of martus became customary in the early centuries to designate those who gave their lives for the Christian faith, and has now passed into our English language as "martyr." This eloquent "witness" of those who died for Christ rather than live without Him became one of the most effective testimonies to the One for whom they died, and made a great contribution to the final triumph of the faith over paganism. This was perhaps the most effective witness that could be made to the lordship of Jesus, either then or now. Such witness is foreign to our present Western experience, but it is startling to think that in other parts of the world more people have died for Christ in our generation than in any other since the Christian era began. I do not refer to those who have died in wars ostensibly fighting to save what we think of as Christian civilization, but people who have been martyred in cold blood in peacetime simply because they dared openly to confess faith in Christ. In a world that has grown increasingly secular and pagan, where the Church's witness has in many areas been weakened by compromise and accommodation to the surrounding culture, the


70

Miller

witness of martyrdom may be the means by which the world will once more be conquered by the faith. And that sort of witness can never be a self-conscious effort to turn persons' attention to the one who makes the sacrifice. No martyr expires saying, "Look at me and see my courage in dying," but rather silently testifies to Him whose "head was crowned with thorns, and that face that was spit upon" for him or her. One last word. The New Testament makes it clear that no "witness" can be effectively made to the world, either by word or by !ife, that is not empowered by the Holy Spirit. Conversely, no "witness" can be heard or rightly interpreted apart from the aid

of the Holy Spirit. All our efforts to be or to speak are vain save as they are "begun, continued, and ended" in Him.

Notes 1. "Olympus," Tlte Columbia Encyclopedia, ed. William Bridgwater and Seymour Kunz, 3d ed. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1963).

2. Ibid. 3. Professor Balmer H. Kelly, in conversation. 4. This statement was made in a lecture at Union Theological Seminary in Richmond, Virginia.

5. See fruitful discussions of "witness" (manus, manureo and related words) by H . Strathmann, TDNT, ed. Gerhard Kittel (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1967); John L. McKenzie, Dictionary of tlte Bible (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1965); Robert Kock, Encyclopedia of Biblical Tlteology, ed. Johannes B. Bauer (New York: C rossroad, 1981); and Xavier Leon-Dufour, Dictionary of tlte New Testament (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1980). 6. H. H. Farmer, The Servant of the Word (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1943), p. 18f.

7. Kittel, TDNT, p. 477ff. 8. Robert Byron, quoted by John Julius Norwich in a review of his Byzantine Achievement in Tlte Spectator 259 (December 19/M, 1987): 74. 9. The difference between recognizing authority and impaning it may be seen in an experience of a friend of mine who, in Chicago's gangland days, was accosted at night by a hoodlum. The man demanded, "Give me a buck!" My friend just handed him a dollar without looking and went on his way. He impaned no authority to the hoodlum. but recormized a certain tvoe of authoritv which the hoodlum oossessed at


Some Observations On The New Testament Concept of "Witness"

71

that time! 10. See Alois Stoger, "Eucharist," Encyclopedia of Biblical Theology. 11. Eugene H. Peterson, Reversed Thunder: St. John's Apocalypse and the Praying Imagination (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1988), quoted from pre-publication manuscript. 12. P. T. Forsyth, Positive Preaching and the Modem Mind (Pittsburgh: The Pickwick Press, 1981), p. 65. 13. John Brown Myers, William Carey (New York: Fleming H. Revell, n.d.), p. 152. 14. Quoted by Dora Greenwell, The Patience of Hope, first published in 1859, new edition (London: Gibbings and Company, 1900), p. 141. 15. Ibid. 16. Letters of John Wesley, ed. John Telford (London: Epworth Press, 1931), 5:16. 17. Ibid., p . 358f. 18. Ibid., 7:114. 19. Ibid., 5:16 20. See John L. Peters, Christian Peifection and American Methodism (Nashville: Abingdon, 1956), Appendix 1. 21. Greenwell, Patience of Hope, p. 142. 22. Forsythe, Positive Preaching, p. 67f.



John 20:22, Once More ROBERT W. LYON According to the Fourth Gospel, on the Sunday evening of the Resurrection--on Easter evening--Jesus appears to His disciples behind closed doors. After His greeting of peace, He confirms His identity by showing them His hands and His side. Then, following a commissioning word the text records that "He breathed upon them and said, 'Receive the Holy Spirit."' This, in turn, is followed by the logion granting authority to the community with respect to the promise of forgiveness (John 20:21-23). The question that always arises in the examination of this text is how this Easter evening event of the insufflation of the Spirit relates to the Pentecost experience recorded in Acts 2: 1- 4. Three general types of explanations are commonly offered, though with significant variations within these three types. To begin with, many speak of two separate bestowals of the Spirit: the first one on Easter evening as recorded in the Fourth Gospel, and the second at Pentecost as we find in Acts 2. The two e vents are separated by fifty days during which the Ascension took place . At first glance this seems to be the most natural interpretation. But for those advocating this interpretation , the agreement ends immediately. The purpose, meaning and impact of the two events are variously explained . Chrysostom (fourthfifth century) related John 20 to the forgiveness of sins, while the event of Acts 2 empowered the church to perform miracles and to raise the dead . 1 Others propose that John 20 concerns individuals in their relationship to the Father, whereas Acts 2 is characterized as ecclesiastical and missionary.2 James M . Boice sees John 20 as especially for the apostolate, while Acts 2 is the promised general outpouring upon the Church.3 H. B. Swete views the latter experience as the sending of the person of the Paraclete , while the Easter event meant the "inspiriting" of his life.4 Westcott concurs with the distinction set out by F. Godet: John answers to the power of the Resurrection, the other to the power of the

Robe11 W. Lyon, Ph.D., is prof essor of New Testam ent interpretation at Asbury Th eological Seminary.

THE A SBURY THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL

VOL

43 No. 1

1988


74

Lyon

Ascension.s That is, one brought the grace of quickening, the other that of enduement. Regarding the two-fold bestowal, E. C. Hoskyns writes, "What the Lord will do invisibly from heaven He here does visibly on earth. The mission is inaugurated but not actually begun .... The actual beginning of the mission lies outside the scope of the Fourth Gospel. There remains, therefore, room for the Pentecostal outpouring."6 Leon Morris does not define the difference between the two events, but says only that John tells us of one gift and Luke another. 7 J. A. Bengel, followed not surprisingly by John Wesley, sees John 20 as transitional and anticipatory, an arrha of Pentecost.8 James D. G. Dunn, in a very thorough and judicious discussion, concludes that for the disciples--and only for them--the baptism of the Spirit (Acts 2) "was a second and distinct work of the Spirit in the spiritual

experience of the first disciples." 9 He further delineates the distinctions between the two experiences by saying that the former

enables the disciples to experience the recreative breath of God (which, he says, was only possible after the Crucifixion/ Resurrection), whereas Acts 2 is the giving of the Spirit according to promise and after the Ascension. These proposals all have one thing in common, namely the recognition that only Acts 2 represents the actual fulfillment of the promise first declared by John the Baptist10 and repeated by Jesusll that the followers of Jesus would be baptized in the Holy Spirit. The particular appeal of this way of interpreting the two passages is the way the two accounts by John and Luke dovetail so well, thereby removing many historical and other problems. A second approach to the two texts was offered as early as the sixth century by Theodore of Mopsuestia, whose view was later condemned by the Second Council of Constantinople in A.o. 553.u It was suggested that in John 20 the disciples did not really have an experience of the Spirit. Rather, Jesus acted only figuratively and by way of promise. The words were purely symbolic of a future gift. The expression was proleptic. For some representatives of this interpretation, part of the argument has involved the suggestion that the aorist labete equals the future though those who advocate this approach would not rest their case entirely on that proposal. This understanding of John 20 was espoused also in the seventeenth century by Hugo Grotiusl3 and a century later by August Tholuck. 14 Two more recent conservatives have also sought to maintain this position. Theodor Zahn suggested that the anarthrous expression pneuma hagion points to the symbolic form of the gift. 15 "The symbolic event (Ger., Handlung) is, therefore, only a drastic renewing of the promise given earlier in words that the exalted Jesus would


John 20:22, Once More

75

send them the Holy Spirit."16 In our own time, G. E. Ladd has asserted that there was only one gift, the one recounted in Acts 2, and that John 20 is "acted parable promissory and anticipatory to the actual coming of the Spirit at Pentecost."17 He derives this in part from the meaning of John 7:39 that the Spirit could not be given until after the Ascension, as well as from the fact that there is no evidence that the disciples entered into their mission until after Pentecost. This second option is particularly attractive because it supports all the rest of the New Testament witness that there is only one bestowal of the Spirit, though that bestowal is described through a variety of metaphors . Those who support this interpretation of John 20 tend to view all explanations of the two-fold bestowal as artificial, unconvincing and unnecessary. The historicity of Acts 2 is not challenged. Therefore, John 20 is to be seen as something other than an actual bestowal. This leads us to the third option, namely, that we ha ve only one bestowal of the Spirit upon the disciples and that John 20 is the writer's own highly theologized version of Acts 2, what is called "the Johannine Pentecost." This view is seldom espoused by conservative scholars who tend to view the historical problems as insurmountable. On the other hand, it seems to be a view assumed as obvious or inevitable b y others. C. K. Barrett, 18 C. H . Dodd,19 R. H . Fuller,20 C. F. D. Moule, 21 Adolf Schlatter22 and Kirsopp Lake23 are representative of those who regard the two texts as divergent traditions of the same event, though some would see different emphases in each. Alfred Loisy goes a step farther when he suggests that John is correcting Luke by substituting the Resurrection gift for the Pentecostal gift.24 To Barrett, it is impossible to harmo nize the two accounts, a view which probably explains why few conservatives have supported the idea that John and Luke can both be reporting the same event. The historical incongruencies are quite obvious: (a) the Johannine e ven t takes place Easter evening, whereas in Acts it takes place fift y days later; (b) the Johannine bestowa l is by the risen but not yet ascended Lord, while for Luke the Spirit is given after Jesus is seated at the right hand of the Father (2:33 ); ( c) Thomas is present in Acts 2 but absent in John 20; and (d) it is also quite possible that the hoi mathetai of John 20: 19 refers only to the inner circle of the immediate disciples (as at the Last Supper) whereas Luke has 120 gathered at Pentecost.is Do these incongruencies doom the prospects of this option? We shall come back to that question. How do we choose from among these three options? To resolve the problem of this passage and its relation to Acts 2, we


76

Lyon

must begin with one fundamental principle of interpretation , namel y, that we must read John according to John and not throug h Lukan lenses. We cannot impose one author on another; we must let John speak for himself. Though we will still have to face the task of relating the text of John to that of Acts, we must fi rs t read John according to John. With this principle in mind, it seems that the second of the three options has the least appeal precisely because it is an attempt to understand John's text within the framework of Ac ts 2. Neither the argument that labete = li!mpsesthe or the suggestion that the anarthrous pneuma hagion carries a special s ignificance has been convincing. But beyond that, this particular reading of the text is not suggested by anything in the text no r by any literary, philological or theological feature of the Fourth Gospel. It derives entirely from the existence of th e account in Acts 2. Reading J o hn by itself, as the primitive Johannine community and perhaps ot hers might have done, we probably would not even propose this explanation of the text. It is proposed e ntirel y in th e light of Acts 2. Nothing in the text itself would indicate that o n that Easter evening the disciples did not receive the Hol y Spirit. Perhaps the only thing th at commends this option is that it rightl y recognizes the witness of the rest of the New Testa ment in ac knowledging only one bestowal of the Spirit. And it rejects the idea that the case of the disciples was different. As we s hall see, there is another and better way of interpreting the text while e ndors ing the "o ne bestowal" motif of the New Testament. The popularity of the first option , namel y, of two separate bes towals o r experiences of the Spirit, suggests it mus t be take n serious ly. It cannot be dismissed simpl y because it is looked at as a necessary approach in view of the desire to prese rve the a uthe nticity of the historical narratives of Scripture. This first optio n (two bestowals) is not purely an apology for Sc ripture, though for some interpreters this may well be a large part of what moti va tes th e ir approach. James D . G. Dunn, who s urely has no desi re to protect the historicity of the na rratives, cautio us ly adopts this interpretation.26 Though he acknowledges the real possibilit y of the third o ption, ultimately his conclusion seems to be rooted largely , though not exclusively, in John 7:39: "for the Spirit had not yet been given , because Jesus had not yet been glorified." The sa me theme is conveyed in 16:7; the departure of Jesus is important, it is "for your good" because only then can th e Spirit be gi ve n . Though man y have argued for an ascens ion of Jesus between 20: 17 and 20: 19, so that the insufflation of verse 22 would indeed be by the ascended Lord (and so dovetailing with Acts 2), Dunn is not persuaded that the Ascension has taken place


John 20:22, Once More

77

in John's narrative. Therefore 20:22 cannot be the fulfillment of the promises in chapters 14-16. Dunn regards 20:22 as the moment of new birth for the disciples. This could take place, he maintains, only after the Resurrection . He rightly views the disciples as the people of the transition between dispensations . In this transition period , he identifies three decisi ve milestones. Prior to the death/ Resurrection of Jesus, the Word dominated their experience and by it they were cleansed (13: 10; 15:3). But until the Resurrection they could not experience new birth, which occurs in 20:22. Then in the third milestone at Pentecost they experience the promise of the Father. The first milestone, then, is before the death/ Resurrection of Jesus; the second, new birth, is after the Resurrection when for the first time the y become Christians; the third, at Pentecost, is when they truly experience the promised baptism of the Spirit. This construct of the disciples' experience has much to commend it, but it raises several serious questions. First, it employs the language and categories of later Christian theology to treat the experience of the disciples. Dunn acknowledges that from Acts 2:38 on we have only the one expe rience of new birth--incorporat ion into the Body of Christ, salvation--upon the occasion of receiving, or being baptized in, the Holy Spirit. But then he employs the term "conversion" (p . 179) and notes that the cleansing spoken of in J3: I 0 and 15:3 cannot mean that the disciples were converted. Conversion, he affirms, took place in 20:22 at the experience of "new birth ." But it is surely a vexing question as to when the disciples were converted. As to the metaphor of cleansing, E. P. Sanders has noted that in some places in rabbinic literature the term "cleanse" means "atone."27 This would suggest some sort of relationship between the disciples and Jesus (and the Father), perhaps involving forgiveness, reconciliation and other terms more associated with Paul. Can one be forgiven , in terms of the new dispensation in Christ, and not be a Christian? Further, John 17:9 suggests that they are Christians before Jesus' death. "I pray for them; I am not praying for the world but for those whom you have given to me, because they belong to you" [italics mine). In addition, the word "already" in 15:3 prevents us from interpreting the verse proleptically . Can it be said that people who, through the ministry of Jesus, belong to God and who have been cleansed by the Word are not in some sense of the word Christians? Again, it is said that prior to the death/ Resurrection of Jesus the cleansing is by virtue of the Word (dia ton logon), and that this is a qualitatively different experience from the new life and new birth through the receiving of the Spirit. While it is true that


78

Lyon

the language of "life" is linked with the Spirit and with the Resurrection of Jesus, in which He overturns death and makes available the !ife of the age to come, yet at the same time we must also draw attention to the fact that John also links "life" with the Word. "The words which I have spoken to you are both spirit and life" (6:63). Similarly, Peter, speaking for the twelve, says, "You have the words of life" (6:68). And throughout the Fourth Gospel !ife is linked with believing: whoever believes has eternal life (3: 15f, et al.). We cannot say that John links life only with the receiving of the Spirit. The almost monumental diversity of language and metaphor in John's Gospel prevents us from mecha nically limiting the concept of conversion and new birth to the receiving of the Spirit--even in spite of the exclusive tone of

3:5. Dunn acknowledges (p. 179) that they are believers, but believers without having received the Spirit. This seems to put a severe limitation on the significance of believing. Dunn is to be followed wholeheartedly when he speaks of the entry on the part of the disciples into the blessings of the new dispensation as "staggered" (p. 182), while at the same time not necessaril y supported in his "three milestones" interpretation of the J ohannine witness. Though not without its own conundrums, it seems much better to suggest that those who believed and who followed , who had been cleansed by virtue of the Word, who belonged to the Father, were indeed what we could today call Christians , that is, followers of Jesus. We may also add that it is possible to suggest that in some nascent sense they may also have had the Spirit, if we cons ider John 14: 17, a notoriously difficult text about which to have any degree of certainty . To begin with, we run into a te xt-critical problem in determining whether estin (present) or estai (future ) represents the primitive text and whether menei should be accented as a present or future verb. So, for the three verbs in this text we ha ve the possibility of one, two or no future tenses. The first one, ginoskete, is clearly present and either of the other two, or both , may also be.28 The problem is further compounded by the fact that, even if we decide text critically for the present tenses, any or all of the three ve rbs may be regarded as proleptic , as futuristic present tenses, so that even with all present tense verbs the text might be rendered, "You will know Him for He will abide with you and will be in you." Certainly in erchomai in verse 18 we have su.c h a futuristic present. Though the latter two verbs of verse 17 will remain in doubt, less doubt surrounds the first one: "You know him."29 However, R. E. Brown30 and o ther commentators prefer the proleptic understanding. Still it may very


John 20:22, Once More

79

well be that we can understand the present tense "know" in the sense that by virtue of their identification with Jesus and their participation in His ministry they "know" the Paraclete, as it In knowing and following Jesus they also were, by "proxy." know the Spirit by which Jesus performs His miracles (Matt 12:28). If we may appeal to another writer not in the Johannine tradition, we note that Luke (10:9, 17) records the disciples as performing the same healings and exorcisms. Through their following Him they were, might we say, under the umbrella of the Spirit. In that sense they do know the Spirit; and in that sense they bore witness to the power of the Spirit. None of this accords with subsequent Christian experience. Their experience cannot be ours, as Dunn says so well. But it is their experience we are trying to understand. Because life is connected with the receiving of the Word and with believing, it is quite possible to say that the disciples "had the !ife of the age to come" prior to the death/ Resurrection of Jesus. As we have noted (John 17:9) they are said to "belong to the Father." And a certain reading of 14: 17 may also allow us to affirm that even before receiving the Spirit (20:22) they do indeed know the Spirit--even though, as we have said, only by proxy. That we should even discuss these matters in these terms assumes that John had, or ought to have had, our questions in mind. In point of fact it is quite difficult to answer the question of when the disciples were "converted." We find no indication from his narrative that this question was part of his agenda. Other considerations cause us to reject Dunn's "three milestones" perspective. He connects the insufflation of 20:22 with the new birth of the disciples, in accordance with 3:5 and 6:63 , as well as Genesis 2:7 where emphysao is also used. However, our context seems to relate to matters other than life and new birth. The preceding verse suggests the motif of this appearance to the disciples has to do first with the confirmation of His aliveness, but then with mission and the power to carry out that mission . "Just as the Father has sent me, I also am sending (or, am about to send) you" [emphasis mine]. And the verse after the insufflation has to do with the transferring of His own authority regarding forgiveness of sins over to them: "Whoever's sins you forgive they are forgiven ...." To interpret the insufflation as the inbreathing of life, rather than the conveying of authority and power, is to do violence to the context. In fact, it is remarkable how similar the context here is with that of Acts 2:4, where the fullness of the Spirit is linked with mission and the power to engage in mission (Acts l :8; cf., Luke 24:49).


80

Lyon

For Dunn and others, the verb enephysesen carries considerable weight. It means "to breath into" and is said to carry the idea of imparting life. Gen 2:7, which describes God as breathing into Adam with the result that he becomes a living being , is cited as the inspiration for John 20:22. Concurring support is elicited from Ezek 37:9, where the breath of God brings life back into the dry bones. On the other side, elsewhere this same Greek verb bears a destructive note (Job 4:21; Ezek 21 :26, 22:21). And in Tobit 6:8 and 11 :11 it relates to a miraculous recovering of sight. So, it does not necessarily mean the imparting of life. Furthermore, Michal Wojciechowski has recently brought o ur attention to the Targums of Gen 2:7 in which the breath of God is not so much the source of life as of the "word" (Fr., parole).31 He notes that according to the Targums of Neofiti, of Onqelos and of Pseudo-Jonathan , the insufflation of Adam means that he has been given the gift of speech. Though these texts are later than the New Testament, they may reflect a tradition that ex isted in the first Christian century. This line of evidence supports one common stream of New Testament witness of the Spirit which links the Spirit with speech and communication . At Pentecost the gift of speech is obvio us . So also is the promise in the first chapter of Acts: "You will receive power when the Holy Spirit has come upon you and yo u will be witnesses to me ..." (v 8). Acts 4:31 concurs: "And all of them were filled with the Holy Spirit and began to speak the Word of God boldly." Again, Acts 4: "Then Peter, filled with the Holy Spirit, said to them" (v 8; cf., Acts 13:9). Though 3:5 and 6:63 link the Spirit with birth and life, the primary significance of the promised gift of the Spirit in chapters 14-16 is that of truth and communication. Three times the Paraclete is referred to as the "Spirit of Truth." In 14:26 the Spirit will teach them everything. In 15:26 He will bear witness to Jesus. He will convict the world of sin , righteousness and judgment (16:8). He will guide them into all truth (16:13). This is how, we propose , John 20:22 must be understood when we see it in the context of verses 2 1 and 23. To interpret the insufflation of 20:22 in terms of 3:5 and 6:63 is to ignore its own context. One other note: the verb elabete, as Bultmann32 and othe rs have noted, is almost a technical term in the early Church for that definitive reception of the Spirit which incorporates one into the Bod y of Christ (cf., John 1:16; 14:17; Acts 2:38; 8:15 , 17; I Cor 2:1 2).33 We suggest, then, that our passage has exactly the same theological significance for John's narrative that Acts 2:4 has fo r Luke's. In both, the bestowal of the Spirit is linked with mission ,


John 20:22, Once More

81

power and authority. Both may be seen as the culminative act of the incarnate Jesus following His glorification. As C. H. Dodd has said, "Accordingly, the gift of the Spirit to the Church is represented ... as the ultimate climax of the personal relations between Jesus and His Disciples."34 This is as true of 20:22 as of Acts 2:4. But what of the historical disparities between the accounts? R. E. Brown has noted, "A willingness to neglect temporal implications for theological significance is not unusual in John."35 He adds, "If John's purpose is forgotten, the attempt to dramatize in temporal scenes what is sub specie aeternitatis creates confusion."36 Historical conundrums abound in the Fourth Gospel. But they must be faced in a way that does justice to Johannine criteria for "truth" and "gospel." While Dunn would agree up to a point, at the same time he reminds us that John's narrative is "Although we cannot deny John's not history gone amuck. concern to impress a theological scheme on a chronological sequence of events, it would not be true to say that the former completely ignores and suppresses the latter."37 This caveat is important, but so, too, is his acknowledgment. In view of John's frequent reference to the coming of the Spirit (7:39 and chapters 14-16), it is much more likely that John would provide us with an account of that bestowal than that he would narrate an otherwise not previously mentioned experience . Dunn's suggestion that John would know of two bestowals, record the promise of one of them, and then narrate the other38 seems less than convincing. Much the more natural understanding is that which sees our pericope as the fulfillment of that promise which is otherwise so important to John's scheme of things. The historical problems are there, as in so many sections of this Gospel, but the y cannot rule over what otherwise seems clearly to be the thrust of John's message. The themes of John's Gospel, the terminology, (especially) the context, as well as the fact that at every theological point this pericope answers to Acts 2:4, all support the view that we do indeed have here a Johannine Pentecost. It is a highly theologized version of that inceptive experience which gave birth to the Church and perfected the work of the incarnate Son.39 This understanding of the pericope makes it very much the culmination of John's record. So we may be permitted to ask one more question. Is it possible that at one stage of the production of this Gospel it was indeed the end of the text? This is not the first time such a question has been asked of the Fourth Gospel. Many have suspected that at some point in the process that produced this Gospel, 20:30f served as the close and that chapter 21 was added either by the author or an intimate colleague. Others have gone


82

Lyon

even further by pomtmg out various redactional elements throughout the Gospel--including dislocations.40 More recently, R. E. Brown has offered a thorough assessment of the matter and has proposed that the Gospel passed through five stages to reach its present form. 41 It is not our purpose here to evaluate such efforts at reconstructing the history of this Gospel, but only to note the common sentiment that more than one hand may have helped in producing our Gospel in its present form. At some point in the process, then , could our pericope have served as the final words of the narrative? If we suppose for a moment that this was so, and if we compare this pericope with Matt 28: 16-20, we find the similarities to be striking. Both record a definitive appearance to the disciples. Both include an indication of doubt (Matt 28: 17; John 20:20). The Great Commission of Matthew is repeated in John (vv The promise of the continued presence of Jesus in 21-23). Matthew corresponds to the bestowal of the Spirit in John . And both Gospels, significantly, end with a saying of Jesus rather that with some sort of summarizing narrative (Luke) or statement of purpose (John 20 and 21 ). E. Bammel finds precedent for this in the Testaments of the Twelve Patriarchs42 and mentions John as having the same kind of ending. In fact, Bammel refers to 20:2429 as "a first supplement" (Ger., ein erster Nachtrag) .43 Everything after 20:23 is anti-climactic and appears to be elaborations of resurrection themes, including the element of apostolic doubt (20:24ff), the corporeality of the risen Jesus (21: 1ff) and the restoration of Peter (21 : 15ff). John 20: l-23 includes all the elements of what we may call "the resurrection package": the tomb is found by women to be empty on Sunday morning (Matt 28: l ff; Mark 16: 1ff; Luke 24: l ff; John 20: 1ff); some interpretive word is provided by angelic representative(s) (Matt 28:2ff; Mark 16:3f; Luke 24:4ff; John 20:20); the doubt of the disciples is noted (Matt 28:16; Luke 24: 11 ; John 20:20); the appearance of Jesus to the disciples as a group (Matt 28: l 6ff; Luke 24:36ff; John 20: l 9ff); a Great Commission (Matt 28: l 9f; Luke 24:47; John 20: l 9ff); and finall y, the promise of power for mission through the promised Holy Spirit who will continue the Lordship of Jesus within history (Matt 28:20; Luke 24:49; John 20:22). To be sure, the Resurrection narratives include other features such as the attempt in Matthew to bribe the people, and in Luke the walk to Emmaus. But the above mentioned items represent the core of our Resurrection accounts. John 20: 19-23 may well have served as a culminative word , if not of this particular Gospel, then of some Vorlage which was incorporated at some stage of the redactional process. It is enough


John 20:22, Once More

83

to note that nothing is missing from the heart of the Resurrection records when Matthew ends as it does, and if John had once ended as I have proposed.

Notes 1. John Chrysostom, Johannem Homil. 87, in Migne, Patrologia Groecae, Vol 61, p. 472. 2. E .g., B. F. Westcott, The Gospel of John (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1954), p. 295. 3. James M. Boice, Witness and Revelation in the Gospel of John (Grand Rapids: Zondeivan, 1970), p. 120.

4. H. 8. Swete, The Holy Spirit in the New Testament (London: Macmillan, 1910), p. 166. 5. Westcott, The Gospel of John, p. 350; F. Godet, Commentary on the Gospel of John , (New York: Funk and Wagnalls, 1886) 2:422.

6. E. C. Hoskyns, The Founh Gospel, ed. by F. Noel Davey (London: Faber and Faber, 1940), p. 547.

7. Leon Morris, Commentary on the Gospel of John (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1971), p. 847. Morris appeals, i.n part, to common Christian experience: "Rather, the Spirit is continually manifesting Himself in new ways" (p. 847). This, however, it should be noted, is not a " manifestation" of the Spirit but a concrete "bestowal" of the Spirit by Jesus. 8. J. A Bengel, New Testament Word Studies (Grand Rapids: Kregel, 1971) 1:726. (Wesley: "This was an earnest of Pentecost.") 9. James D. G . Dunn, Baptism in the Holy Spirit (Philadelphia: Westminster, 1975), p. 178. (Cf. his Jesus and the Spirit [London: SCM Press), p. 96.) 10. Matthew 3:11; Mark 1:8; Luke 3:16; John 1:33. 11. Acts 1:5; 11:16. 12. Henry Denzinger and Adolf Schonmetzer, eds., Enchiridion Symbolomm (New York: Herder, 1965), p. 150. (ou dedoken outois pneuma hagion, a/la schemati monon enephysi!sen.) 13. Hugo Grotius, Opero omnia Theologica in Tres Tomos, Tomi 2, Vol. 1, n.p., 1679, p. 570. ("Sicut passionem suam futurom signis aptus proefigurovit, ita & missionem Spiritu Sancti, qui vento comparotur Actomm ii.2. ")


84

Lyon

14. According to R. E. Brown, The Gospel according to John, 13-21 (Garden City: Doubleday, 1970), p. 1038. 15. Theodor Zahn, Das Evangelium des Johannes (Leipzig: Deichert, 1912), p. 679. 16. Ibid. 17. G. E . Ladd, A Theology of the New Testament (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1974), p. 289. 18. C. K. Barrett, The Gospel according to St. John (London: SPCK, 1955), p. 474f. Cf. his The Holy Spirit in the Gospel Tradition (London: SPCK, 1958), p. 159. 19. C. H. Dodd, The Interpretation of the Founh Gospel (Cambridge: The University Press, 1953), p. 227; Historical Tradition in the Fourth Gospel (Cambridge: The University Press, 1963), p. 144. 20. R. H. Fuller, The Formation of the Resurrection Namitives (New York: MacMillan, 1971), pp. 140, 214. 21. C. F. D . Moule, The Holy Spirit (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1978), pp. 31, 76. 22. Adolf Schlatter, Das Evangelium nach Johannes, Vol. 3 in Erliiuterlungen zum Neuen Testament (fubingen: Calwer, 1962), p. 296. Schlatter does not mention Acts 2 in connection with John 20, but the nature of his comments indicates clearly that John 20 represents the bestowal of the promised gift. 23. Kirsopp Lake, Additional Notes in Vol. 5 of The Beginnings of Christianity: Th e Acts of the Apostles (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1966), p . 121. 24. A. Loisy, Le Quatrieme Evangile (Paris: A. Picard et fils, 1903). 25. Others who equate John 20 with Acts 2 include: George T. Montegue, The Holy Spirit: Growth of a Biblical Tradition; R. Bultmann, The Gospel of John: A Commentary; Alan Richardson, An Introduction to the Theology of the New Testament; Leonhard Goppelt, Theology of the New Testament; R. E. Brown, Th e Gospel according to John, 13-21; Eduard Schweizer, "pneuma" in Kittel, TDNT; Helmut Thielickc, The Evangelical Faith, Vol. 3; R. Schnackenbury, The Gospel according to St. John, Vol. 3. The list could be extended considerably. 26. Sec Chapter 15, " The Johannine Pentecost?" in Baptism m the Holy Spirit, pp. 173-182. 27. E . P. Sanders, Paul and Palestinian Judaism (London: SCM, 1977), p. 161 , n. 66. 28. The options on the basis of the tenses are: (a) You know Him, for He abides with you and is in you. (b) You know Him, for He abides with you and will be in you. (c) You know Him, for He will abide with you and will be in you.


John 20:22, Once More

85

29. So almost all translations; that of Monsignor R. Knox is an exception. 30. R. E. Brown, Gospel, p. 639. 31. Michal Wojciechowski, "Le Don de L'Esprit Saint dans John 20:22 scion Tg. Gn. 2:7," New Testament Studies 33(April, 1987): 291. 32. R. Bultmann, The Gospel of John (Philadelphia: Westminster, 1971) pp. 76, 616. 33. Similarly the words didumi and dechomai. 34. Dodd, Interpretation, p. 227. 35. Brown, Gospel, p. 1015. 36. Ibid., p. 1014. The entire paragraph may well be read carefully with much profit. 37. Dunn, Baptism, p. 176. 38. Ibid., p. 177. 39. R. Schnackenburg supports John's dating of the event and says that Luke has placed the event at Pentecost to pick up on certain motifs. Hence, he says, "Johannine Pentecost" is an anomaly and misnomer. It is not our purpose here to pursue that question, but only to speak for the identity of the two events. 40. See W. F. Howard, The Fourth Gospel in Recent Cn"ticism and Interpretation, revised by C. K. Barrett (London: Epworth, 1955), pp. 166ff; 297ff. 41. Brown, Gospel, pp. xxiv-xl. 42. E. Bammel, "Das Ende von Q," in Ventas Verborum; FS Gustav Stahlin. ed. Otto Bocher and Klaus Haacker (Wuppertal: Rolf Brockhaus, 1970), p . 47. 43. Ibid.



Book Reviews Matera, Frank J. What Are They Saying About Mark? New York / Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press, 1987. ix, 115 pp . $4.95 paper. ISBN 0-8091- 2885-3. Frank Matera studied at St. Bernard Seminary, Rochester, NY, and the University of Louvain, Belgium , before completing doctoral studies in biblical literature at Union Theological Seminary, Richmond, Virginia. Professor Matera is known by his published Gospel research. He serves as a priest of the archdiocese of Hartford and is professor of New Testament at St. John's Seminary, Boston. Like other entries in the "W hat Are They Saying A bout... ?" series, Matera's work ai ms to introduce stude nts to the "lay of the land"--in this case, in Markan studies. Matera reaches as far back as Wrede but concentrates on the key figures in the stud y of Mark's Gospel over the last twenty-fi ve yea rs. He revi ews their work and attempts to discern the present direction of Marka n studies in five major areas: (I) se tting, (2) Christology, (3) treatment of the disciples, (4) composition, and (5) narrative of the Gospel. A brief statement of conclusions is followed b y endnotes and suggestions for further reading ( 44 entries, the earliest from 1959). The presentation is consistently clear and non-polemic. While the work is aimed primarily at seminar y and college students beginning serious biblical study, persons with broad acquaintance with biblical scholarship will find Matera's stud y useful. Perso ns wanting a more exhaustive re view of histo ry of Markan studies will need to consult a work like Sean P. Kealy's, Mark 's Gospel : A History of Its Interpretation (New York/ Ramsey: Paulist Press, 1982), though Matera's mastery of the interplay between the iss ues addressed is superior to Kealy's , in my judgment. In Matera's view, Mark is written from and to a Roman setting just prior to 70 A.D. b y (as well as anyone else) John Mark , associated in complex ways with Peter. Charting the immense shock waves from Wilhelm Wrede's discovery of the "Mess ianic secret," Matera concludes the precise function of this theme in the Gospel remains itself a secret. Wrede's most important contribution was the insistence that Mark's Gospel is at heart a Christological statement, not material for a life of Christ. Ultimately stemming from the Wrede agenda, the attempts to establish a corrective Christology in Mark have made their greatest contribution , says Matera, in demonstrating the centrality of the


88

Book Reviews

su ffering and death of Jesus to any ad equate understanding of He doubts an alleged theios aner concep t Jesus in Mark. illumina tes the problem a nd questions the ability to reco nstruct the heresies at which Mark's "correction" would be aimed. In his opi nion, the efforts usuall y result in an unnecessary polarization of the Son of Man/ Son of God themes which are to be seen as complementary, not contradic tory. In Matera's view, the secrecy motif relates to the theme of the suffering Son of God, the key to Mark's royal Christology. Matera is unconvinced by those who argue Mark 's treatment of the disciples as a polemic. Instead , Mark writes with pastoral motives, lead ing his community to "follow Jesus" past the lures a nd dange rs of th eir paga n setting. The disciples' ignorance is primaril y due to the fact that they know Jesus only apart from His death and Resurrection. This introd uctory work does not intend to elaborate and defend at length a position on the Gospel of Mark . But nowhere do Matera's basic conce rns appear more clearl y than in hi s d isc uss ion of the compos ition of the Gospel, the issue reall y at the hea rt of al l the oth er questions. In Matera's judgmen t, the last centur y of Markan scholarship has come to a n impasse for lack of ev idence. Eve ry c hap ter ends with a "no co nsensus" verdict from conventional approaches (source, form and redaction c riticism) to the Gospel's c hief ques tions. Matera concludes that it is not now poss ible to identify wi th confidence th e sources used in the compos ition of Mark . He is skeptical of app roaches which in volve overly speculative reconstruc tions, lack convincing external evidence, fragm ent the book , a nd fail to produce a consensus answer to the basic questions rai sed by the Gospel. Matera finds th e most promising approach in reading the Gospel as story, using the tools of the newer literary and In Matera's mind this does not mea n rhetor ical c riticism. abandonin g the questions of source, form and redaction. Rath er he urges focus on a more immediate agenda, the read ing of the Gospel and its literary units as wholes as a prerequisite for returning to historical questions. But he warns against neglecting historica l iss ues in a purely literar y stud y of the text. I think his assessment is correc t. In my judgme nt it is particularly fitting that a review of Matera's work should find its way into a volume honor ing Dr . Robert A. Tra ina. Dr. Traina's work proceeds on premises similar to Matera's rega rding the necessity of focusing on the literary fo rm of th e text as it is and as a whole, and of eschewing approaches which f ragment the composition and in volve overly


The Asbury Theological Journal

89

speculative reconstructions as the very framework in which the research will proceed. Dr. Traina was doing the "new" literary and rhetorical criticism and publishing its theory and results years before the terms were brought to biblical studies. The impasse documented by Matera is due in part to the inclination of biblical studies in the academy to be confined by the most recent fad. It remains to be seen whether literary/ rhetorical critics will achieve any greater agreement regarding major issues in Markan study than those using other methods. Here again, Dr. Traina's comprehensive approach to biblical study anticipates the problem by incorporating all critical methods necessary to understand the text as a whole. If there is any hope for consensus, one suspects it is in a convergence of methodologies. This is the direction in which Matera's review of current Markan studies, his own published work, and that of Robert A. Traina point. DA YID L. THOMPSON, PH .D. Associate Professor of Biblical Literature Asbury Theological Seminary Mann, C. S. Mark: A New Translation with Introduction and Commentary. Anchor Bible, vol. 27. Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1986. 714 pp. $20.00. ISBN 0-385-03253-6. This is Mann's second contribution to the Anchor Bible series; he co-authored, with the late W. F. Albright, the volume on Matthew, which appeared in 1971. That volume has generally not been well received by the New Testament scholarly community, because of its overemphasis upon purely technical matters, its lack of attention to theological issues, and its insistence upon the priority of Matthew, a view that is overwhelmingly rejected by New Testament scholars. In the present commentary, Mann continues to argue for the minority opm10n regarding synoptic ongms, adopting the "Griesbach Hypothesis," which posits that Mark is an abridgement of Matthew (the first Gospel to be written) and Luke. This understanding of synoptic origins stands over against the commonly-held "Two-Source Hypothesis," viz., that Mark was the first Gospel, and Matthew and Luke used Mark and a sayings source (usually labelled "Q") as the basis for their Gospels. Actually, Mann's position is a somewhat modified form of the Griesbach Hypothesis, since he allows the possibility of the priority of Luke, and even suggests that a radically revised form


90

Book Reviews

of the Q theory could find a place in his reconstruction of synoptic origins. The fact that the Griesbach Hypothesis has not been generall y accepted by New Testament scholars leads Mann to engage in an extensive defense of the theory. Yet Mann presents virtually no new arguments for the Griesbach Hypothesis beyond those put forth by W. R . Farmer in his classic work , The S ynoptic Problem . These arguments are fraught with as many improbabilities and implausibilities now as when they were offered by Farmer in 1964. The Two-Source Hypothesis remains the theory that best explains the relationship between the synoptic Gospe ls, while creating the fewest problems. This is not to say, however, that the Two-Source Hypothesis does not contain difficulties. In fac t, the value of these challenges to the Two-Source Hypothesis is that they point to the necessarily tentative and provisional character of any critical reconstruction, including one so broadly accepted over the past century as the Two-Source Hypothesis . This recognition is in part responsible for the recent emergence of lite rar y critic ism in the study of the Gospels and Acts. It is clear that the adoption of the Griesbach H ypothesis has far-reaching implications for the interpretation of Mark , includin g such questions as the Sitz im Leben out of which the G ospe l of Mark arose, the purpose of the Gospel as reflected in Mar k's redactional activity, and the ways in which Mark's redac tion of Matthew and Luke informs the meaning of individual passages of the Gospel as well as the theology of the Gospel as a who le. And Mann addresses each of these issues; in fact, this co mme ntar y is the first major attempt to interpret the Gospel of Mark from the perspective of the Griesbach Hypothesis. Unfortunately, the answers Mann gives to these questions are less than satisfac to ry. Mann is convinced that Mark, the auditor of Peter, began the compilation of data in Rome, but actuall y wrote his G ospel (primarily on the basis of Matthew and Luke) in Palestine sometime between A.D. 60-66. He argues that the G ospel best suits this setting because (a) its urgency reflects the chao tic climate of antebellum Palestine, and (b) the redactional te nde nc ies of Mark (esp. chap. 13) assume the state of affairs in the Palestinian Christian community during that period . Into this situation Mark thrust his Gospel , edited to emphas ize the hope fo r the continuation of the Palestinian church, on the basis of the victory of Jesus its Lord. But Mann's evidence is strained . Neither the no te of urgency in the Gospel nor the putative redactional movements of Mark necessarily point to this setting. Granting Mann's proposal, it is difficult to understand why the Gospel of Mark was writte n at all ,


The Asbury Theological Journal

91

since Matthew and Luke were already known and used in Palestine, and they address the concerns which Mann identifies behind Markan redaction. Further, if Mann's reconstruction is accurate, Mark omitted many passages from Matthew and Luke which speak to these concerns, while bringing over intact extraneous material simply because Mark felt bound to the tradition. Mann's attempt to interpret the Gospel by an examination of Mark's redaction of Matthew and Luke is generally not productive. The reasons are obvious: the purpose Mann ide ntifies behind Markan redaction is too general to inform the specific interpretation of individual passages; and Mark's redaction of his sources is essentially a redaction of omission, and it is difficult to discern theology primarily on the basis of the omission of material. This massive commentary contains many helpful insights and much technical background information. Yet, given the many excellent commentaries on Mark, and the tendentious character of this volume, most students of Mark would be better served by investing in more reliable works. DA YID R . BAUER, PH. D. Assistant Professor of English Bible Asbury Theological Seminary Achtemeier, Paul J. The Quest for Unity in the New T estament Church. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1987. xii , 132 pp. Paper. ISBN 0-8006-1972-2. According to Paul J. Achtemeier, professor of New Testament at Union Theological Seminary in Richmond, Virginia, and the editor of Interpretation, unity was an ideal to be stri ved for, not attained in the New Testament church as described by Luke in the Book of Acts. Luke had only a second-hand knowledge of the early church. He reworked his sources, which were fragmentary and incomplete , according to his preconceived (biased) theological idea about how church deve loped. Achtemeier focuses his investigation on the relationship between Paul and the Jerusalem leadership. In Galatians 1-2 Paul mentions his two visits to Jerusalem . Achtemeier identifies the first visit (Gal 1:18-21) with Acts 9:26; and the second (Gal 2:110) with Acts 11: 1-18, when the Jerusalem leadership, under Peter, agreed that the Gentiles could become Christians without circumcision. Even though Acts did not mention it, Paul was


92

Book Reviews

there. He accepted this agreement and was encouraged to carry on Gentile missions under such agreement. Later, under the influence of James, the Jerusalem leadership imposed the decree of the Apostolic Council (Acts 15) upon the Gentile Christians. Even though Acts mentions Peter, Paul and Barnabas as participating in that Council, in fact they did not. When the decree was brought to Antioch, Peter and Barnabas accepted it. But Paul considered it to be a breach of the earlier agreement and rejected it. This brought about the separation of Paul and Barnabas. Contrary to the report in Acts, the decree actually caused division in the early church, even in the Gentile missions . Everywhere he went, Paul was opposed for his theological pos1t10n. Attempting reconciliation with the Jewish Christians, Paul made a collection of money among the Gentiles Christians for the poor in Jerusalem. This final attempt ended in failure. This book is well organized. The argument is easy to follow . At each step the author usually spells out the methodology, and indicates the next step to follow. Adequate endnoting, including those of opposite views, is another helpful feature of the book . There are some attractive interpretations of certain biblical passages. Some questions, however, can be raised. Achtemeier highlights the fact that James informed Paul of the decree of the Apostolic Council at their last meeting in Jerusalem (Acts 2 1:25). From this he argues for Paul's absence at the Council. However, even if Jam.e s knew Paul was present at the Council, it would still be natural for him to mention that in the context of Acts 2 1:25. If we take the "we" section of Acts seriously, as many reputable sc holars do, then we cannot agree with Achtemeier that Luke had only second-hand and very limited knowledge of Paul. If Luke traveled with Paul for a while , his presentation of Paul's activities would not have been mere speculation or wishful thinking. Paul never mentions the decree of the Apostolic Council in his epistles. This, however, does not necessarily indicate that he did not know about it or resisted it. His treatment of the issue of food offered to idols in 1 Corinthians 8 and 10 agrees with it in principle. Probably his support of the decree was misinterpreted by so me as his attempt to please men. So he asked the rhetorical question "Or am I trying to please men?" in Gal 1:10. If, as Achtemeier claims, "Paul ended his career an isolated figure, whose theological emphases were destined for swift decline in the decades to follow" (p. 61 ), then why were so many epistles of Paul canonized in the New Testament? JOSEPHS. WANG, P11.D. Professor of New Testament Asbury Theological Seminary


The Asbury Theological Journal

93

Aune, David E. The New Testament in Its Literary Environment. Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1987. 262 pp. $22.95 . ISBN 0-664-21912-8. Aune's work is the eighth contribution to the Library of Early Christianity series edited by Wayne Meeks. The purpose of this series is to explore the Jewish and Greco-Roman contexts within which the New Testament and early Christianity arose. The high quality and practical value of this series has been further enhanced by Aune's contribution. Aune surveys four types of literature in the Jewish and Greco-Roman milieu: biography, historiography, letters and revelatory literature, relating them to the Gospels, Luke-Acts, Christian letters and apocalypses. One of the added bonuses of Aune's presentation is that he does not limit himself to the New Testament writings but includes Christian writings of the same genres from the second century . Aune flies in the face of much twentieth - century New Testament scholarship with its strong aversion against classifying the Gospels as biographies. His survey of biography in the Greco-Roman world reveals a genre characterized by great diversity through a coalescence of numerous literary forms and even other genres . Having laid a strong foundation through his broad representations from ancient biographical writings, Aune makes a strong case for the Gospels as biography. One feature which somewhat weakens Aune's case, however, is his tendency to presuppose the "assured results of critical scholarship" regarding the historical reliability of the Gospels. Aune seems to subscribe to the theory that the Gospels are largely "fictitious" works of the early church and provide little, if any, support for knowing the historical Jesus. Even though Aune correctly warns that "it is illegitimate to allow theological assumptions to determine the results of literary criticism," and assumes "that the Evangelists wrote with historical inte ntions" (p. 64), he goes on to state, "To claim that the Evangelists wrote biography with historical intentions, then, does not guarantee that they preserved a single historical fact . It does suggest that they restricted the scope of invention to that appropriate to the biographical task as popularly understood" (p. 65). The overlooked consideration, which may also contribute to the lack of consensus on the genre of the Gospels, is that the Gospels convey a unique (divine/human) event which not even the most diverse literary genre can adequately contain or convey. Such a unique event, of course, would have no antecedents in biographical literature except as unhistorical fictions to which it


94

Book Reviews

would naturally, but erroneously, be compared. Another weakness is Aune's totally unquestioned assumption of the Two-Source Hypothesis. He reflects no awareness of the recrudescence of the Griesbach Hypothesis which has received added impetus with the renewed emphasis upon literary criticism in recent years. It seems that Aune would have done himself and his readers an even greater service had he reflected upon such issues in the light of his excellent portrayal of the literary environment of the New Testament. This criticism is generally true for the entire scope of the book. Rather than using the findings of his study of the literary milieu of the New Testament to examine afresh the basic questions of New Testament study , Aune presumes results of critical scholarship which are increasingly questioned . One might question Aune's tendency to presume the fictional nature of much of Acts, but he has clearly and, I believe, unquestionably demonstrated that Acts falls into the literary genre of historiography. This is a healthy balance for the prevailin g perspective which views Acts primarily as a theological treatise. Aune's work with letters is probably the strongest portion of the book. Not only does he provide a locus for Christian letters within the literature of the Greco-Roman world, but he also integrates them with the prevailing conventions of Greco-Roman rhetoric and diatribe. One of Aune's strong contributions here is to show that rhetorical conventions make it far more difficult to assuredly define the opponents of the writer of a New Testament letter. What have previously been taken as arguments of "opponents" may be nothing more than rhetorical devices used by the writer to defend or strengthen the argument. Aune's discussion of apocalyptic writings reflects an excellent grasp of the leading edge of the field. Unfortunately, however, he succumbs to the prevailing socio-literary analysis of apocalyptic which allows no room for the possibility of genuine revelatory experiences. The book of Revelation, consequently, is seen as one more example of Israelite-Jewish and Greco-Roman revelatory literature. While it is clear that Revelation utilizes the literary style of revelatory literature, should there not be room for the possibility that a genuine mystical experience lies behind the literature? Aune also accepts the prevailing perspective of Revelation as eschatologically oriented without considering the possibility that it reflects a vision of the immanence of the Kingdom in ongoing history. One of the most helpful features of Aune's work, as with the entire Library of Early Christianity, is the provision of a list of excellent resources for further study, delineated by subtopics for


The Asbury Theological Journal

95

each chapter. One of the most disconcerting f ea tu res stylistically is an excessive and intrusive use of parenthetical remarks. In spite of its several flaws, Aune's work is required reading for any serious student of the New Testament, a task that will be not only informative and enlightening, but also stimulating and provocative of new insights and understandings. M. ROBERT MULHOLLAND, JR., TH.D. Professor of New Testament Asbury Theological Seminary Hayes, John H. and Frederick Prussner. Old Testament Theology: Its History and Development. Atlanta: John Knox Press, 1985. 290 pp. $15.95, paper. ISBN 0-8042-0146-3. Frederick C. Prussner is the primary author of this work. He died in 1978 before its publication. Prussner served as professor of Old Testament at the Candler School of Theology, Emory University. The book represents a significant part of his doctoral dissertation submitted to the Divinity School of the University of Chicago in 1952. It remained the task of John H. Hayes, currently professor of Old Testament at Candler, to expand and update Prussner's work for publication . As the title indicates, the purpose is to trace the historical development of Old Testament study from the time of Luther to the present. This monumental undertaking is approached by a review of more than fifty theologians and an examination of their presuppositions and methodological pursuit of the biblical text. The scope of the work is far-reaching and inclusive. It elucidates the difficulty of speaking of the Old Testament theology at all. This is a landmark volume in Old Testament study a nd represents a much needed-treatise in the scholarly arena. Hayes and Prussner have attempted to present a fair, unbiased description of the various Old Testament academies in as thorough a way as possible. Such thoroughness is perceived in the treatment that each theological position receives. Not infrequently the authors trace and explicate the various precursors that influenced a particular Old Testament theological stance. Each position is carefully considered within its historical context such that the reader is able to determine the forces at work during a particular time period and, hence, understand better the process and perspectives of Old Testament study. From the emergence of Protestant Scholasticism, with its primary concern to make the Bible "fit" preconceived dogmatic orthodoxy, Hayes and Prussner


96

Book Reviews

demonstrate the evolution of theological thought along a reactionary axis: the response of Pietism-Romanticism and Rationalism to Scholasticism; the subsequent rise of Hegel's Idealism and the conservative response of the early nine teenth century. The authors retell the story well and illustrate the need for Old Testament scholarship to step beyond the bounds of particular parochialisms to the wider appreciation of the contributions and presuppositions of other perspectives. The major part of the book (presumably written by Prussner) indicates a sympathetic, unbiased presentation of the material. It seems unfortunate that such an engaging approach to the material is deemed unnecessary b y Hayes in the final section of the book where, time and again, viable theological positions are unfairly dismissed and personal interests are peddled. Old Testament Theology is a much-needed volume. It is

written competently with much research (as one might expect from a doctoral dissertation) and presented in a lucid style whic h makes for interesting reading. Without doubt, this book will be of inestimable value both to teachers and students in the academy as well as to pastors in the parish, notwithstanding the rather unworthy update of the final twenty-five pages . ALAN J. MEENAN PH .D. Los Angeles, California




Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.